By Matthew Hooker

           For the duration of the COVID-19 emergency, North Carolina corporations may conduct shareholders’ meetings completely via remote communication technology, pursuant to an executive order by Governor Roy Cooper.[1] This order temporarily resolves an ambiguity in the North Carolina Business Corporation Act pertaining to remote participation in shareholders’ meetings, allowing North Carolina corporations to address pressing business matters without raising concerns about the validity of actions taken at wholly virtual shareholders’ meetings.[2]

            The global crisis stemming from the COVID-19 pandemic[3] has brought the global, national, and local economies to a collective screeching halt.[4] For those businesses that have sought to continue operations, those operations now look vastly different. In the United States, currently at least forty-two states, the District of Columbia, and Puerto Rico (together representing around 316 million people) are under various forms of “stay-at-home” orders.[5] Now that avoiding even small groups and staying at home have become the new normal, virtual conferencing platforms using video and screen sharing technology have quickly emerged as vitally necessary to businesses’ continued operations.[6]

            Corporations in North Carolina have been forced to deal with the question of whether shareholders’ meetings may be conducted completely remotely and still be valid under North Carolina law. As drafted, the North Carolina Business Corporation Act is not entirely clear on this issue; it can be interpreted as providing that a valid shareholders’ meeting may only be held at a physical location. To illustrate, the Act refers to holding both annual and special meetings “in or out of this State at the place stated in or fixed in accordance with the bylaws”[7] and requires that a valid notice of a meeting include the “place” of the meeting.[8] Under certain circumstances, the Act allows shareholders to participate and vote in those meetings “by means of remote communication.”[9] But the Act is silent as to whether the entire meeting may be held virtually with no physical place of meeting.[10]

            To bring clarity to this issue in light of the COVID-19 pandemic and the need for business to be conducted remotely as much as possible, North Carolina Governor Roy Cooper issued an executive order on April 1, 2020 authorizing and encouraging remote shareholders’ meetings.[11] This order appears to apply equally to annual meetings and special meetings. Under the order, a corporation’s board of directors may determine that all or part of a shareholders’ meeting may be held solely via remote communication.[12] This type of remote shareholders’ meeting is permissible under two conditions: (1) shareholders must be allowed to participate and vote under the existing remote participation and voting statute,[13] and (2) all shareholders must have the right to participate in the meeting via remote communication.[14] Governor Cooper’s executive order resolves the ambiguity of the North Carolina Business Corporation Act by providing that a “place” of a meeting within the meaning of the Act can include a meeting where all shareholders participate through remote communication (i.e., there is no physical “place” of the meeting).[15]

            But the order goes even further. It also permits a corporation’s board of directors to limit the number of attendees physically present at a shareholders’ meeting in order to ensure conformity to other state gathering restrictions.[16] In other words, it appears that not only may a board of directors call for a completely remote shareholders’ meeting, but the board could also hold a meeting at a physical place but then prohibit shareholders from physically attending and force shareholders to attend remotely.

            This executive order provides North Carolina corporations with clarity during the COVID-19 crisis. It enables them to conduct meetings and business that involve shareholders without fear that actions taken at a remotely held shareholders’ meeting will be deemed void.[17] In the midst of a global crisis such as COVID-19, it is important that corporations can continue to operate as best as they can without compromising the health and safety of shareholders, among others.

            However, not only does Governor Cooper’s order resolve this important issue for corporations as long as the COVID-19 emergency lasts, but it also reveals that the North Carolina Business Corporation Act needs updating. The current version of the North Carolina Business Corporation Act was enacted in 1989 and thus does not comprehend many of the vast technological shifts and developments of the 21st century.[18] Although the Act was amended in 2013 to allow shareholders to remotely participate in shareholders’ meetings,[19] the addition of that provision only explicitly allows remote participation; the Act overall still seems to contemplate some sort of physical location where the meeting is actually held. If anything, that 2013 amendment creates ambiguity rather than resolving confusion. Interestingly enough, Governor Cooper’s executive order actually concludes by advising that the order should not be construed or interpreted as suggesting that a shareholders’ meeting held wholly via remote communication would not otherwise be valid if not for the executive order.[20] Thus, even Governor Cooper’s order seems to subtly acknowledge the lack of clarity within the North Carolina Business Corporation Act on this matter.

            The world has changed greatly since 1989—and even since 2014. With key provisions of the North Carolina Business Corporation Act now over three decades old, it may be time for the North Carolina legislature to revisit the Act. Modern technology has opened up a world of possibilities for corporations, and the Act should reflect that. Remote communication options are just one example. These technologies are becoming increasingly prevalent and dependable—even when no global health crisis exists—and the law should not inhibit progress in the corporate context. In fact, Delaware has long permitted shareholders’ meetings to be held solely via remote communication.[21] Amending the North Carolina Business Corporation Act will align North Carolina with other leading states in corporate law. Ultimately, this will enhance North Carolina’s viability as a modern, attractable location for entity incorporation as well as facilitate existing domestic corporation’s continued leverage of the digital world.


[1] See N.C. Exec. Order No. 125 (Roy Cooper, Governor) (Apr. 1, 2020), https://files.nc.gov/governor/documents/files/EO125-Authorizing-Encouraging-Remote-Shareholder-Meetings.pdf.

[2] See id. § 1(A).

[3] See WHO Director-General’s opening remarks at the media briefing on COVID-19 – 11 March 2020, World Health Org. (Mar. 11, 2020), https://www.who.int/dg/speeches/detail/who-director-general-s-opening-remarks-at-the-media-briefing-on-covid-19—11-march-2020.

[4] See, e.g., Harriet Torry & Anthony DeBarros, WSJ Survey: Coronavirus to Cause Deep U.S. Contraction, 13% Unemployment, Wall St. J. (Apr. 8, 2020, 10:00 AM), https://www.wsj.com/articles/wsj-survey-coronavirus-to-cause-deep-u-s-contraction-13-unemployment-11586354400.

[5] Sarah Mervosh et al., See Which States and Cities Have Told Residents to Stay at Home, N.Y. Times, https://www.nytimes.com/interactive/2020/us/coronavirus-stay-at-home-order.html (last updated Apr. 7, 2020).

[6] See, e.g., Akanksha Rana & Arriana McLymore, Teleconference Apps and New Tech Surge in Demand Amid Coronavirus Outbreak, Reuters (Mar. 13, 2020, 3:33 PM), https://www.reuters.com/article/us-health-coronavirus-teleconference/teleconference-apps-and-new-tech-surge-in-demand-amid-coronavirus-outbreak-idUSKBN21033K.

[7] N.C. Gen. Stat. §§ 55-7-01(b), 55-7-02(c) (2019).

[8] Id. § 55-7-05(a).

[9] Id. § 55-7-09(a).

[10] Cf. § 55-7-05(a) (requiring notice of the place of the shareholders’ meeting).

[11] See N.C. Exec. Order No. 125, supra note 1.

[12] Id. § 1(A).

[13] See N.C. Gen. Stat. § 55-7-09.

[14] N.C. Exec. Order No. 125, supra note 1, at § 1(A)(1)–(2).

[15] See id. § 1(B)(2).

[16] Id. § 1(B)(3).

[17] See id. § 1(C).

[18] See 1989 N.C. Adv. Legis. Serv. 265 (LexisNexis).

[19] See N.C. Gen. Stat. § 55-7-09 (2019); 2013 N.C. Adv. Legis. Serv. 153 (LexisNexis).

[20] See N.C. Exec. Order No. 125, supra note 1, at § 1(D).

[21] See Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 211(a) (2020).

By: Kelli A. Alces*

Introduction

The board of directors has outlived its purpose.  The board is theoretically responsible for directing the management of a corporation, for monitoring its senior officers, and for making significant business decisions.  The typical directors of the largest multinational corporations devote about seventeen hours per month to the governance of the corporation.[1]  So responsibility for the success or failure of the firm lies with a group of professionals, the board of directors, who work part time to monitor the firm’s business, and management, who receive almost all of their information about the firm secondhand.

Certainly the board of directors monitors corporate officers, particularly the CEO, and makes significant business decisions for the firm.  But it is the senior corporate officers who are responsible for the day-to-day operation of the company and who are most involved in its business decisions.  When the board must vote on a particular matter of corporate business, officers and experts selected by the officers brief it on the subject.[2]  Despite being the focus of corporate law’s accountability for corporate decision making, the board of directors relies heavily on the senior corporate officers it is supposed to monitor and lacks the time and expertise to challenge those officers in order to contribute valuable independent business judgment.[3]

There are a number of other groups that exercise oversight over the firm. Creditors, for example, reserve oversight power in their contracts with the firm.  Those contracts often give creditors a veto over some corporate decisions if the company is in a poor financial condition, and creditors often use the declaration of default threat to influence officers’ and directors’ decisions.[4]  Shareholders may exert control over the company through their ability to elect directors and enforce officers’ and directors’ obligations to the firm. Also, shareholder estimation of managerial performance is one component of stock price, which is a significant component of executive compensation.[5]  In firms with unionized labor forces, union representatives are able to influence corporate decision making through their ability to threaten a strike.[6]  Among these corporate monitors, directors are often the ones paying the least attention to the firm on a regular basis, even though they are ultimately responsible for the success of the firm.  The board of directors, as an institution, has failed the modern public corporation with widely dispersed share ownership.[7]

The inability of the board of directors to adequately perform its intended functions exacts serious costs.  A system that relies so heavily on one governance structure is left vulnerable when that structure fails.[8]  Further, placing a strong emphasis on board accountability when boards cannot be meaningfully responsible for corporate decision making leaves those harmed by corporate scandal without recourse.  Money spent on pursuing litigation against corporate directors is wasted, by and large, as directors are shielded from personal liability and yet the law still looks to directors for accountability for corporate decisions.[9]  Our expectations for boards of directors of large public companies far outweigh what such boards can realistically accomplish.[10]

Numerous corporate law scholars have critically examined the structure and functions of the board of directors[11] and have evaluated the relative success of various board compositions.[12]  These commentators have alternatively praised and criticized the board for its ability to monitor management and maximize shareholder wealth.[13]  The academic and business communities have failed to reach a consensus about how exactly the board should fit into the corporate governance structure, what its role and level of influence should be, how it is supposed to work toward the goal of shareholder wealth maximization, and to what extent the board should be responsible for a failure to meet those ends.  Although the members of the corporate law community have reached a variety of conclusions, they all rest on the assumption that a board of directors is both necessary and desirable.

This Article challenges that basic assumption.  It argues that the board of directors in a large public corporation is ineffective to perform the functions assigned to it and should thus be eliminated in favor of a governance system that more accurately reflects corporate decision making.  Corporate officers and the investors and parties in interest that are essential to the firm’s daily operation and capital structure—the real corporate decision makers—should perform the functions assigned to the board, so that the now-vestigial board of directors can completely wither away.

Abolishing a formal board of directors would not spell the end of corporate governance.  In the absence of a board, corporate constituents would be permitted to enforce their rights against the corporation and management directly.  Their contracts with the firm could evolve to fill gaps in corporate decision making.  Because these constituents already exercise significant oversight of the firm, they are well equipped to perform the monitoring and management functions of the board.  Because a post-board firm is so different from what we have had to date, this Article suggests a path that could lead to the gradual elimination of the board governance structure.  This Article is meant to be the first step on a path toward the evolution of the corporate form away from the use of a board of directors and highlights regulations it might be prudent to remove.

Because current legal and regulatory regimes do not appear to permit the wholesale abandonment of the board of directors immediately, this Article also proposes a less radical change to the corporate governance structure—one that would allow it to more accurately reflect corporate decision making within extant legal regimes.  In particular, the Article suggests implementing a board dominated by representatives of the firm’s investors—at least the firm’s creditors and shareholders.  Major bank lenders would be represented on this “investor board,” indenture trustees would represent bondholders, and an equity trustee[14] could represent the shareholders.  Such a board would monitor senior officers directly and also make major corporate business decisions (according to the powers reserved to the board and the investors sitting on it through their respective contracts).  The diversity of the board members’ individual interests assures that they are less likely to settle into too close of a relationship with management, but instead will actively protect their investments, and thereby, best protect the corporation.  The divergence of interests will provide a check on overreaching.

This Article proceeds in three Parts.  Part I explains the conventional justifications given for the current board structure.  It reviews the evolution of the board to its present form and considers the purpose of the modern board of directors.  Modern corporate law favors a board primarily intended to monitor corporate officers.  A board of directors is also expected to perform a more limited management function by advising senior officers about significant corporate decisions.  Part I explains that the current board structure suboptimally allocates authority and oversight in public corporations.

Part II proposes significant changes to the board of directors.  It sketches a post-board firm, suggesting how to monitor corporate managers in different, more direct ways.  Recognizing the hurdles to completely and immediately abolishing the board of directors, Part II suggests how an evolution toward a post-board firm might begin with a board of directors made up of investor representatives.  Such a board would more accurately reflect the balance of power in corporate decision making and would set the stage for an evolution away from the use of a formal board of directors.  A more accurate understanding of corporate decision making will lead to more direct accountability for those responsible for the firm’s financial success.

Part III considers various obstacles to the Article’s proposals.  Corporate and securities laws confine the structure of the board and prevent some kinds of market evolution.  Though several problematic aspects of board governance are the products of market forces, it is the law, not the market, that prevents corporate governance from evolving past its current form and away from the use of a vestigial board of directors.  The market has chosen to render the board of directors weak and relatively meaningless and to empower corporate constituents and officers to dominate corporate decision making.  Part III proposes relaxing or removing laws that prevent the governance structure from expanding upon and formalizing the reality of corporate decision making.

I.  Why a Board of Directors?

Surely, there are reasons, perhaps good ones, for choosing a governance structure in which a board of directors bears primary responsibility for the direction of the management of “[t]he business and affairs of every corporation.”[15]  The fact that the board has evolved to its present form reveals market preferences against a strong board in the extant legal framework.  It is important to understand that evolution before criticizing the board’s diminished role.  Insights from organizational theory also shed light on our current board structure.[16]  This Part will examine each of those observations in order to better understand why the modern corporate board of directors looks and acts as it does.  It will also explain why the current formulation of the board prevents it from effectively performing its assigned tasks.

A.            History and Evolution of Board Structure and Purpose

American corporations have always had boards of directors.[17]  This tradition emerged from English trading companies, which used governing boards to represent business owners in joint stock companies.[18]  The board was to sit at the top of a parliamentary system of corporate governance.[19]  Originally, boards managed the day-to-day business of the firm.[20]  This was because they were made up primarily of controlling shareholders and managers selected by those shareholders.[21]  Particularly in family-run firms, the founders and their closest friends and relatives were the owners and managers of the firm and so constituted the board of directors.

Even into the early 1900s, when corporations were just beginning to grow and move past the realm of family-run local businesses, corporate boards were chosen by dominant majority shareholders and were often composed of firms’ managers.[22]  As corporations grew through the 1970s and shareholding was divided among more widely dispersed shareholders, CEOs, rather than shareholders, began to choose the board members.[23]  Shareholders elect directors, but once an increasing number of firms failed to have a controlling shareholder in place, the CEO was able to run the daily operations of the firm and could handpick nominees to the board.  The result of that change was that the board was effectively inferior to the CEO it was supposed to supervise.  The board’s role “became advisory rather than supervisory.”[24]

That state of affairs persists and continues to shape board composition and effectiveness.  Because shareholders cannot coordinate to exercise control over the firm and its management,[25] the CEO and senior officers have an advantage when it comes to choosing directors.  So chosen, and without intimate knowledge of the firm, the board of directors cannot exert control over the daily business of the firm and cannot easily monitor management.  Directors owe their positions to the officers they are supposed to supervise, and they rely upon those same officers for the information they use in supervising them.[26]  Social pressures also define the relationship between the board and management[27]—“board traditions in the United States make outsiders invited guests, not policy makers.”[28]

Still, there must be some role for the board.  It is, after all, where legal accountability for corporate decision making lies.  The board of directors may not be particularly effective, but it is not yet dismissed as a mere figurehead.  Modern corporate law has settled on a notion of a “monitoring” board.[29]  A monitoring board is composed mostly of independent directors, those not having close personal or financial ties to the firm.[30]  It is supposed to pay attention to management to the extent it can, to discover bad faith or incompetence, and replace officers as necessary.[31]  Board independence is supposed to be optimal for performance of the monitoring function.  An independent board, theoretically, will not have strong ties to individual managers and thus will be comfortable challenging and removing them.[32]  It will force senior officers to defend their choices and will make them notice irregularities or improprieties in management’s conduct of corporate business.[33]  The independent monitoring board has been criticized, however, for being ineffective at performing even the most basic monitoring function.[34]  The next Subparts consider the monitoring and management functions of the modern monitoring board and evaluate the board’s effectiveness in performing those functions.

B.            Monitoring

Directors are supposed to appoint the CEO, perhaps advise the CEO on the selection of other senior officers, and evaluate the work done by the senior management team.[35]  To the extent corporate governance law and practice now favor a monitoring board, the board functions are supposed to be separate from senior management, and the board is supposed to be a largely independent supervisory body.[36]  Rather than holding senior officers directly responsible for corporate well-being, even though officers control the day-to-day business of the company, Delaware law has long placed primary responsibility with directors, providing that directors are responsible for monitoring officers and so are ultimately responsible for whatever corporate decisions the officers make.[37]  The board, then, is conceived of as an independent, relatively distant body charged with overseeing the very highest levels of corporate decision making.

1. Board Independence

In designing a monitoring board for the public corporation, federal and state law as well as public listing exchanges have required that only “independent” board members be allowed to perform certain functions in public companies.[38]  For example, mandatory audit and compensation committees must be made up of independent directors.[39]  Indeed, firms appear to have better and more accurate financial reporting when independent directors with accounting expertise sit on their audit committees.[40]  The majority of board members must be independent.[41]  Independent directors are those having little or no personal or financial relationship with the firm.[42]  The rationale for using independent directors is the expectation that they will not be sympathetic to management, will feel free to challenge managers as necessary, and will remove them without compunction if senior officers are not performing optimally.  For instance, independent directors may not “have a personal financial stake in retaining management.”[43]  If the directors do not have a personal stake in keeping management on board or can keep a certain distance and remove themselves from the company’s business, they will be able to respond dispassionately to problems that arise, prioritizing shareholder wealth maximization.

This definition of “independence” is not clear and guarantees only a certain kind of autonomy from other corporate operations.[44]  Independent directors are neither necessarily socially independent from management nor unsympathetic to the concerns of senior officers.[45]  Professors Gilson and Kraakman note that in trying to find an appropriately independent outside director, shareholders may have succeeded in finding directors who are more independent from shareholders than they are from management.[46]  This is because independent directors are still primarily senior officers of other corporations, making them unlikely to monitor senior officers of the companies on whose boards they serve more than they want to be monitored themselves.[47]

Further, it is difficult, if not impossible, to give independent directors strong incentives to monitor carefully.[48]  Any sort of compensation that tracks corporate or management performance would undermine the very independence required.[49]  If the board is supposed to be a truly independent, distant monitor, then giving directors personal ties to the firm’s finances might make them too much like the managers they are supposed to monitor.  It would truly duplicate the role of officers except that the supervisors, the directors, would only work part-time.  To the extent we rely on reputation to constrain outside directors or to give them incentives to monitor conscientiously, we must remember that those directors are essentially chosen by the CEO.  The directors’ reputations, then, must have more currency with the CEOs that they are supposed to monitor than with the shareholders who passively, and perhaps inattentively, elect them.[50]  Independence for the purpose of monitoring management is, therefore, difficult to achieve.  And even if it were possible, it might not be ideal.

Board members are at a disadvantage when it comes to monitoring officers because they rely on those officers for the information they use to monitor.[51]  If the employee tells her employer why she is doing a great job and gives the employer the information needed to assess the job she is doing, the boss cannot really make an independent judgment about the employee’s performance because all of the information comes from the employee.[52]  This problem with the monitoring structure became manifest during the recent financial crisis.[53]  Independent monitoring boards were not able to discover the serious problems with decisions officers were making and were unable to prevent the collapse of financial firms.[54]  Still, we regulate with an eye toward more independence in board composition,[55] even as it becomes clear that truly independent boards lack the knowledge of the firm that might be necessary to assess managerial performance.

In an article written twenty years ago, Gilson and Kraakman suggest that the market should develop a pool of professional directors to respond to these problems.[56]  They propose that academics and other outside consultants make themselves available to serve on corporate boards and that these “professional directors” devote themselves full time to service on the boards of a handful of companies.[57]  These directors would be beholden only to the shareholders, primarily institutional shareholders, who elect them.[58]  Such a system could create real independence from management in the board and could also result in board members who could invest more time in learning about the companies they supervise.  Unfortunately, the market has not yet evolved toward such a system.  As regulators continue to press for independent, outside directors and those directors are no less likely to be sympathetic to or chosen by management, it is difficult to see how the monitoring board is likely to change.

2. How the Board Monitors

Determining board composition is only one part of designing a board that is able to monitor management.  It is also important to understand how the board is supposed to monitor management and what expectations we have about the board’s monitoring.  We must then try to appreciate how well-suited the board of directors is to performing that level of monitoring.  Understanding the hierarchical, collegial, and probabilistic monitoring described by organizational theory can be useful here.  Hierarchical monitoring contemplates a situation in which the supervisor has the same information as the subordinate actor and can make superior, independent decisions based on more sophisticated knowledge, understanding, or expertise.[59]  This occurs in standard employer/employee relationships and throughout the corporate hierarchy.[60]  Collegial monitoring occurs when the monitor does not “have superior information, or less bias when evaluating the available information.”[61]  In a system of collegial monitoring, managers do not stand as inferiors to their monitors.[62]  Finally, probabilistic monitoring is relatively passive.  Probabilistic monitors respond only when a problem has occurred and try to discern whether the party they are monitoring is responsible for the problem.[63]

The corporate governance monitoring structure is, at various times, hierarchical, collegial, and probabilistic, with directors often acting as more detached, irregular monitors than one would expect given their position at the top of the corporate hierarchy.[64]  For instance, director monitoring is hierarchical when directors decide whether to retain a CEO or which CEO to appoint because they may have sufficient information to make a better decision and obviously lack some of the strong biases the CEO or other senior officers would bring to the decision.  In that situation, the directors’ decision supersedes the preferences of others and their decision is final.[65]  However, directors lack the time and attention hierarchical monitors usually devote to their task.  Directors usually receive their information from officers[66] and so cannot be regular hierarchical monitors because the information the directors have is not as good, let alone superior to, the information officers use to make decisions on a daily basis.  Directors are just not as informed about the day-to-day business of the firm—and they are not expected to be.

Most director monitoring of management is collegial.  That is, directors learn from officers why the officers recommend a particular course of action and officers are not perceived as inferior to directors when the board makes most of its business decisions.[67]  Rather, the officers present an idea to the board and advise directors and then the directors ask questions to determine if they agree with the officers’ judgment.[68]  Directors may consult outside experts (perhaps the same experts officers consulted) to reach as clear an understanding as officers have—not a clearer one.  Directors have to rely heavily on officers for the judgment and information they use in performing their monitoring tasks.  The collegiality between the monitors and the monitored is not metaphorical, but real.  As mentioned above, directors are usually officers of other companies; directors and officers are colleagues and kindred spirits.[69]  Their professional and personal relationships establish a collegial norm for their interaction in governing a corporation.[70]

Directors also engage in some probabilistic monitoring.  Because directors are not always informed about the daily operations of the firm, they cannot know exactly what officers do every day and arguably have little or nothing to do with most decisions officers make.  Directors could not possibly anticipate every problem that may arise and may not know what has caused the difficulties the company faces.  While we expect them to catch big problems and to head off serious financial disasters, directors are not always able to do so.  This occurs, in part, because the board’s oversight responsibility is limited.  The board is only required by law to ensure that reporting mechanisms are in place so that it will hear about serious violations of corporate policy or the law, but the board is not expected to press beyond those systems to discover potential malfeasance.[71]  Also, board members only meet occasionally and are not regularly at the firm observing standard practices.  Because the board only works for the corporation part-time, its members cannot know most of what happens at the highest levels of management.  When a serious problem arises or the company’s value falls precipitously, the board has often been unaware of the potential problem and thus unable to do anything to prevent the crisis.[72]  After the dust has cleared, the board must act as an ex post, probabilistic monitor and must try to determine whether the problem occurred because of the incompetence or dishonesty of the senior officers, or whether it was the result of blameless market- or industry-wide difficulties.

3. How the Board Should Monitor

Given that we expect shareholders to engage in probabilistic monitoring of directors—the best shareholders can do because of collective action problems and their relative lack of information[73]—it seems that the board should be designed to perform closer, more direct monitoring of senior officers.  Collegial monitoring of management by the board is probably the norm.  Both directors and officers are supposed to be working toward the goal of shareholder wealth maximization.  Directors may be somewhat less biased than officers in certain matters, whether because of directors’ “independence” or because they were not part of the decision making up to that point.  Otherwise—because of the problems with board independence mentioned above—board members are no less biased than officers, and so, in the interests of “getting along,” they are most likely to try to reach a consensus with officers over major corporate decisions requiring director approval.[74]

The legislative and regulatory emphasis on board independence might suggest that legislators want directors to engage in hierarchical monitoring.  If the board of directors is supposed to be in charge and the proverbial “buck” is supposed to stop with them, it seems as though corporate governance law favors more hierarchical monitoring of management.  To the extent we ask directors to engage in hierarchical monitoring, we are really asking them to make management decisions because we want them to replace officers’ judgment with their own.  Management is a separate and quite limited role of directors.[75]  Expanding monitoring responsibility and authority too far turns monitoring into an affirmative management obligation.  That is not consistent with the policy choice to limit the board’s management responsibility to a very few significant decisions, and to leave officers with primary responsibility for the day-to-day operation of the firm.  This tension suggests that a board of directors is not actually designed to be an effective hierarchical monitor—and we may not want it to be.

If hierarchical monitoring of senior officers by part-time directors is not possible in most situations, then we must consider collegial and probabilistic monitoring sufficient.  Because shareholders and financial institutions (the latter functioning as both shareholders and creditors) perform probabilistic monitoring of directors[76] and, in some ways, of officers, it seems redundant to have so many layers of “watchers,” unless each additional layer adds something essential.  The board of directors, as currently constituted, is not better suited to hierarchical monitoring than attentive shareholders, creditors, or even labor representatives would be.  As a collegial monitor, the board is not independent enough or knowledgeable enough to exercise distinct decision-making authority in a meaningful way.  The board may be able to challenge the senior officers by asking difficult questions of them about decisions they propose, but it still relies on senior officers for information and guidance about the most efficacious course of action for the corporation.  At best, the board provides a skeptical body to which senior officers must justify their decisions.  This function, while valuable, could just as easily be performed by other parties in interest such as shareholders or creditors.  In fact, in some situations, the senior officers may have to justify decisions to other constituents more often than they have to answer to the board, because those constituents, or their representatives, closely monitor the day-to-day business of the firm in order to protect their contractual rights against it.  As currently constituted, it is hard to see how the board is uniquely qualified to monitor senior officers or corporate business.

C. Management

The board of directors is also supposed to perform a management function.  While not in charge of managing the day-to-day business of the firm, the board is supposed to have the ultimate say on various major corporate issues, such as whether to bring certain lawsuits on the company’s behalf, whether to sell the corporation or to buy another firm, whether to issue dividends to shareholders, and what the corporation’s capital structure should be.[77]  While we have moved more toward a monitoring board over the last forty years or so,[78] the management function of the board cannot be ignored.  The board is expected to make significant management decisions, albeit with the advice of the senior officers and other experts.  Perhaps more importantly, the board performs an advisory function, offering advice and opinions to management about general business concerns.[79]  This advisory function has come to dominate the board’s role when the corporation is healthy.[80]  This Subpart will consider what the board’s management function is, what we may want it to be, and how well suited the current board structure is to making important decisions about the management of the firm.

While most boards of public corporations are now made up of a majority of independent directors, some inside directors sit on all boards.[81]  These inside directors help to set the agenda and help to advise outside board members about the business’s proper course of action.[82]  For many years now, it has been commonplace for the CEO to serve as the chairman of the board of directors.[83]  That means the CEO sets the board’s agenda and calls meetings.[84]  In most instances, inside directors’ work is most important to the board’s management function.[85]  The inside directors know more about the firm’s day-to-day business as well as its relationship with the various parties with whom it contracts.

The board’s very independence may, paradoxically, hinder its ability to make independent business decisions.  As noted above, the board has to rely heavily on inside directors for information and judgment to reach what ends up being a consensus with management.  Professors Gilson and Kraakman point out that outside directors “rarely exercise their judgment today, except during crises, not only because they lack the time and the incentives to do so, but also because board meetings are dominated by a management ethos of forced collegiality and agreement.”[86]  Independent directors are ill equipped to second-guess the decisions of management in a meaningful way.  Not only are they dependent on inside directors for information, but they are kept from “posing hard questions and framing strategic alternatives” which could allow them to “be drawn into real discussions of company policy and might well reject management’s views when warranted” by social and professional norms and personal sympathy with the positions of the company’s officers.[87]

One circumstance stands out as an exception to the general inability of independent directors to exercise meaningful and independent business judgment.[88]  When an acquirer approaches a corporation, the judgment of independent directors becomes vitally important.[89]  Because inside directors have their careers at stake in a potential sale of the company and it is their management of the firm that is being challenged, the “omnipresent specter that a board may be acting primarily in its own interests, rather than those of the corporation and its shareholders”[90] taints any decisions they may make about the takeover bid, and courts will conduct a review of the decision before affording it the benefits of the business judgment rule.[91]  Outside directors are granted more deference when decisions about mergers are reviewed by courts.[92]  In the takeover context, outside directors play an important role and are expected to make judgments about the future, or demise, of the company mostly independent of insiders.[93]  This is one area where the expertise of a board of directors without close personal or financial ties to the firm may be useful, particularly to the extent that that board may represent the shareholders’ interests in maximizing the value received for their shares.[94]

Because of the heavy reliance on inside directors and other officers to perform the board’s management function outside of the takeover context, a board of directors does not clearly constitute a separate, additional decision-making body.  The board can only do so much, in addition to what senior managers have already done, and it really only serves as a backstop, or a final quality check, before a major decision is finalized.[95]  In order for a board of directors to be worth the time, expense, and effort it represents, it should perform a function that is both valuable and distinct from the work others are already doing.  Some would argue that this special function is the work the board performs by mediating among the various parties that have claims against the corporation’s assets.[96]

If the firm is a nexus of contracts,[97] or a nexus of relationships among people and entities, then managing those relationships is an important responsibility of the board.  The board must balance the requirements of loan covenants against shareholder expectations for profit maximization and dividend payments, all while honoring other contracts into which the firm has entered.  The board must determine how to advance the shareholder interest in profit maximization in the face of relevant laws and regulations that constrain the firm’s business activity and its ability to take investment risks.  A working corporation has a number of moving pieces, and those managing the corporation must take care that those pieces do not collide in a way that will do harm to the firm.

Mediating between corporate constituents requires a solid working knowledge of the rights each party has against the corporation and the corporation’s reciprocal obligations.  The board must understand which parties can enforce which rights in what circumstances and how each set of rights fits—or possibly conflicts—with others.  Because senior officers often negotiate the firm’s contracts on its behalf,[98] they have more intimate knowledge of the deals than the board and may have to explain the interactions of the different relationships to the board.  Again, the board must rely heavily on the senior officers it is supposed to independently monitor in order to do its job.  When the board is asked to make big decisions that involve mediating among various interests, it is simultaneously supposed to be supervising officers’ work in setting up the various contracts in the first place and in making the decisions that have led to the firm’s current position.

Meanwhile, corporate constituents do not sit idly by when significant corporate decisions are at stake.  They work to influence board and officer decision making by threatening to stand on their rights or to use their powers to remove or replace officers or directors.[99]  Institutional creditors are a helpful example.  Major loans from banks include detailed covenants that dictate the firm’s capital requirements and its ability to distribute dividends in certain financial conditions, and that give lenders certain powers over corporate decision making.[100]  If the corporation violates a covenant, the lender may declare a default[101]—a declaration that can have serious consequences.  A default on one loan can, by itself, constitute a default on others[102] and cause a number of obligations to become due and payable immediately, which might lead to the firm’s bankruptcy.  Lenders do not want to declare a default any more than the corporation wants them to, but a creditor can use the threat or at least the right to declare a default as leverage to convince management that it should make certain decisions the creditor would prefer.[103]  A creditor might threaten to declare a default unless a corporate restructuring officer of its choosing is appointed or unless the CEO is replaced with someone the lender trusts and prefers.[104]  At the same time, shareholders can enforce their preferences by electing a new board or selling their shares.[105]  Shareholders might prefer that the board pursue a different course of action or may prefer that the board issue a dividend, while creditors, through the power reserved in their covenants, may be able to block the decisions shareholders would prefer.  The necessary mediation among various corporate constituents can be a significant component of the board’s management of the firm, particularly when considering decisions that may affect the firm’s capitalization or capital structure.[106]

The board’s role in these situations is, ideally, to favor the management decisions that are most likely to maximize profits without violating the law or running afoul of the firm’s contractual obligations.  The business judgment rule protects the board from liability for the manner in which it decides to strike that balance.[107]  The board’s role here might serve an important purpose when, for example, creditors and labor unions are both lobbying for particular positions that might compromise shareholder interests and shareholders are not otherwise adequately represented.  To the extent the board can juggle the claims and interests of various corporate constituents while working toward maximizing the firm’s wealth, it can serve an indispensable function for the corporation.

The board’s management, however, is not the best or the most direct way to perform the mediation function.  Because it must be brought up to speed about the relationships at issue before it can even begin to deliberate,[108] the board is not particularly well-situated to make a final decision and must rely heavily on the judgment of others more involved in the day-to-day business of the firm.  There is no reason to believe that the board’s judgment would be superior under those circumstances.  Further, the board does not directly manage most of the firm’s relationships with and among various constituents on a regular basis.  It only weighs in on particularly significant decisions.

When the firm is doing well, the board’s management role is very limited and it defers much more to the judgment of officers.[109]  In reality, the board’s most useful role may be as a group of experienced, collegial consultants available to advise officers about various business matters.[110]  Board members might provide useful connections to the business community or to particular groups with interests in the corporation or its business.[111]  They might have connections to government regulatory bodies that affect the company’s business.  These functions may be useful, but they do not make up a management role responsible for operating a business.  These advisory, or “relational,” functions could be performed by hired professionals or consultants and need not be contained in the body legally responsible for operating the corporation’s business.[112]  To the extent the firm relies on connections with governmental offices or agencies, there may also be ways to maintain connections by retaining certain people as consultants or counsel to the firm without placing those symbolic ornaments on the firm’s governing body.

The firm’s senior officers and managers work with various parties in interest to manage the firm’s relationships with its investors and the outside world.[113]  It is not outside board members, but officers, midlevel managers, and in-house counsel who work most directly with corporate constituents and perform the mediation function.  The board plays only a very limited role in mediating among the corporation’s constituents.  Those constituents take an active role in protecting their own interests and are able to influence management decisions that are important to them.  The day-to-day business of the firm—and so the state of affairs that leads to any decisions the board is asked to make—is largely determined by the interaction of corporate constituents with the firm’s managers.  The board does not perform a meaningfully independent role in the bulk of very important corporate decision-making situations.

Ronald Coase would predict that if we could simply allow corporate constituents to talk with one another when their interests conflict and allow managers to balance the various contracts with the firm between points of conflict, we might reach better outcomes than if we involve a relatively ill-informed third party.[114]  That does not mean transaction costs would be zero, of course, only that a number of transaction costs would be eliminated so direct bargaining could produce better outcomes.  For that reason, it may be appropriate to ask whether the board is in a particularly good position to perform the mediation function: is the board better suited to the task than others, and is a board-centric governance structure justified by the rather insignificant role we see for the board in practice?  The governance structure this Article ultimately proposes contemplates just that kind of communication between the corporation’s parties in interest while allowing the vestigial board to wither away.

II.  Moving Toward the Elimination
of the Board of Directors

Maybe the board structure is not all that many hope it could be, or intend for it to be, but that might not matter if it is still a useful second-best alternative.[115]  The problems with the existing board structure are significant, however, and matter very much to the extent they impede the ability of corporate investors to constrain the agency costs inherent in the corporate form.  The goal of reducing those agency costs has been the preoccupation of corporate law and scholarship for at least the last eighty years.[116]  Corporate monitoring boards are advisory at best and are not designed to bear the weight of responsibility placed on their shoulders by corporate law.  If enough people care about corporate accountability, it should be vitally important to find a way to meaningfully identify and respond to the behavior of the parties actually making decisions for the firm.  By erroneously believing that the board is in that decision-making position, our efforts to improve corporate law and practice are essentially impotent.  The failure of more independent boards to adequately control agency costs is an example of the difficulty the market and reforms have found in trying to fix corporate governance problems by tweaking the monitoring board.[117]  Understanding the reality of corporate decision making and developing a governance structure that openly acknowledges it is essential to providing more efficient, effective corporate management and to ensuring that various forms of effective accountability will be available for investors interested in corporate wealth.

I propose a corporate governance paradigm shift that would result in the eventual elimination of the board of directors.  Because eliminating the board of directors would be a dramatic change in the corporate governance structure—and one that is arguably not possible under extant law[118]—I offer a description of an intermediate step, a so-called “investor board.”  An investor board would be a board of directors made up of representatives of various corporate constituents, including shareholders, creditors, and senior managers.  The makeup of a particular investor board would correspond with the needs and true decision-making structure of each individual company.  Scholars have criticized some corporate governance reforms as requiring a one-size-fits-all board structure despite the fact that different companies have different needs.[119]  The suggestion of an investor board responds to those concerns by providing a blueprint various public corporations can use to design a board of directors that responds to their particular capital structures and the needs of their dominant constituents.  Such a board would accurately reflect the negotiations and relationships the board is expected to mediate.  It would be able to resolve conflicts among corporate constituents directly and knowledgeably.  Most importantly, an investor board moves us further toward an evolution of corporate governance that discards the vestigial monitoring board of directors in favor of a fluid, dynamic governance structure that accurately reflects decision-making power and authority within the modern large public corporation.

Path dependence may have taken us too far down the board of directors road without considering whether the board is necessary and whether the same objectives could be achieved without a board.  As I develop a framework for an investor board in this Part, I will explain at each stage how a component or advantage of the investor board can serve as a valuable step toward the elimination of the board.  I will then explain why progress down this evolutionary path would represent a significant improvement in corporate governance and decision making.

A.            Accurately Reflecting Corporate Decision Making

Part I detailed corporate law’s expectations for the corporate board of directors and explored reasons why those expectations may not be met by the current composition of corporate boards.  The contemporary board does not effectively achieve its stated purposes because it is both too independent to be an effective management body and not independent enough to be an effective monitor.[120]  In coming to terms with the realities of corporate decision making, we may appreciate that certain parties in interest are able to exercise more authority over corporate decision making than others.  Corporate managers, for instance, have much more influence over corporate business than directors can,[121] and creditors may be in a better position to directly influence managers’ choices than shareholders.[122]  By striking or threatening to strike, labor unions may be able to hold up the entire enterprise regardless of what business choices may be best for corporate wealth.  Allowing these parties to interact directly with each other when their interests conflict, and otherwise acknowledging their influence over corporate management in enforcing their contracts with the firm, may lead to a more accurate understanding of corporate decision making and may result in the more effective performance of the tasks currently assigned to the board of directors.  An important first step to eliminating the board is acknowledging that reality and putting those parties in formal monitoring positions with an understanding of their rights and responsibilities that corresponds to their relationships with the firm.

1. The Basic Structure of an Investor Board

An investor board would be made up of representatives of major corporate creditors, a shareholder representative, and, perhaps, labor representatives or others significant to the corporation’s business.[123]  Members of that board would be determined by the significance of their role in the corporation’s life or capital structure.  For example, significant senior creditors and indenture trustees of significant bond issuances would be granted board positions in their loan documents.  The notion of an investor board assumes a shareholder representative like the equity trustee, but, absent a single representative, the company’s largest shareholders could assume positions on the board or get together to select a representative.  A board so composed would be a more effective monitor of senior officers because its members would be less sympathetic to those officers, as well as less socially or professionally entangled with them.  Such a board would also know more about the decisions those officers may make on a daily basis, particularly as those decisions may affect the interests of the various member constituents in the corporation.  Because these parties already serve as effective monitors to a large degree, moving them to the position envisioned for the board could allow the corporation’s governance structure to more accurately reflect the reality of accountability on the ground.  While the investor board would start as a formal replacement for the monitoring board of directors, we may find that in time, the dynamic of the investor board is such that it need only meet to consider certain significant issues.  Over time, we may also find that a governance structure that assigns key constituents different but interlocking and complementary rights no longer resembles a formal board of directors at all.

Without a formal board of directors, the focus of the firm’s decision making would shift to senior officers.  An investor board could capture the important role of senior officers while also balancing their control over decision making against the monitoring powers of significant corporate investors.  For example, senior officers could sit on the investor board and hold voting power for the purpose of reaching important business decisions confronting the firm.  Senior officers make the big decisions about a corporation’s business, and lower-ranking managers make the day-to-day decisions that allow the company to realize the business plan and strategy promulgated by senior officers.  Those business decisions and policies are carried out and prioritized under the influence of the corporate constituents who would exercise oversight on an investor board.  A board composed of senior officers and influential parties in interest may do a better job of reaching management decisions because its members would have more intimate, first-hand knowledge of the corporation’s business than the current monitoring board.

2. Balancing Interests

The key to successfully redesigning the board in this manner is to make sure that the powers of all of the participating parties are equitably and appropriately balanced.  It must be clear what the goal of corporate decision making is supposed to be and how decisions will be reached to that end.  The corporation must also clearly decide what decisions require the input of which parties and who will have what degrees of control in particular situations.  A lot of these issues are already settled in investors’ agreements with the firm.  It will be important that no members of a board composed of corporate constituents are able to exercise more power than they would under their contracts with the firm, and that they will not be able to extract rents from the corporation at the expense of corporate wealth or the protected rights of other constituents.  Senior officers will be responsible for making most business decisions, with the investor board coming together only infrequently to make game-changing decisions such as whether to file bankruptcy or how to respond to a takeover attempt.  For instance, one creditor may already be able to veto a decision to hypothecate more corporate assets or take on additional debt, but its decision to do so may be checked by strong preferences of other, more powerful creditors, or the extent to which the corporation needs the new loan to stay afloat or pursue an important business opportunity.  Shareholders may be able to exert pressure by threatening to avail themselves of their rights to change management personnel or by signaling problems to the capital markets (and so the credit markets) by devaluing the stock through exit.

To some extent, the relevant parties have reached a balance considered optimal because they have negotiated rights and powers with the corporation and each has negotiated knowing the extant and possible rights of others.  Creditors have already reserved the power over the corporation they deem necessary.  They understand how the powers assigned other creditors, shareholders, or significant parties in interest may conflict with theirs or how those other parties may be able to exercise more power in some situations.  Similarly, shareholders understand that they have certain powers over corporate management and have the ability to vote on some corporate decisions, but that they have little control over the activities of officers.  Shareholders also realize that creditors may have more influence over corporate decision making during times of financial distress because those enhanced powers are expressly reserved in loan covenants.[124]

The contracts defining these investors’ rights in and powers over the corporation already fix an important part of the corporate governance structure.  Through the implementation of an investor board, those contracts could evolve to account for their enhanced authority and so eventually fill remaining gaps in corporate decision-making authority.  Eventually, those agreements could so completely define the interaction of particular parties at important moments in the corporation’s operation that a formal board of directors will be unnecessary.  The parties may exercise influence over various decisions, or those with particular concerns can confer as necessary and otherwise monitor management through the enforcement of their agreements with the firm.

3. Adjusting Shareholder Power

Indeed, it is the role and powers of shareholders that would require the biggest change to current corporate governance practice if an investor board were adopted.  Perhaps shareholders’ greatest power over corporate decision making is their ability to elect the members of the board of directors.[125]  If the board becomes a group composed of investor representatives and senior officers, then the shareholder power to elect board members is certainly diminished if not eliminated.  Two important shareholder protections must remain: shareholders must be able to choose an important part of the board and shareholder interests must be specifically represented as effectively as those of other corporate investors.  As to the first point, shareholders should be able to elect the senior officers to the investor board.  As mentioned above, a few senior officers could sit on the board for the purpose of advising and voting on business decisions.  Shareholders could select those officers and perhaps even elect the CEO.  That way, shareholders would maintain some power over corporate personnel.  Upon the elimination of a formal board of directors, shareholders could maintain this authority over the choice of senior corporate managers.  On the second point, particular shareholder representation—to counter creditor representation—would be required.  Some may argue that this shareholder representation is what the board is supposed to do now.  The shareholder representation envisioned by an equity-trustee structure is different because shareholders are not responsible for balancing corporate business concerns or making ultimate business decisions.  The shareholder representation on an investor board would focus on doing the shareholder job as it is assigned to shareholders, not running the corporate business.  The equity trustee can be a zealous advocate for shareholder interests, with a voice that will be appropriately balanced with other interests.  That scheme leads to better and more direct representation of the shareholder interest than the current board provides while still allowing corporate officers to make the business decisions for the firm.

In prior work, I have suggested a way for shareholders to find meaningful, sophisticated representation: an equity committee, made up of the corporation’s largest shareholders, that supervises and works in concert with an equity trustee who is responsible for representing shareholder interests to management.[126]  The equity trustee could sit on the board and represent the shareholder interest in wealth maximization to management and other corporate decision makers.  It could negotiate with other board members on behalf of shareholders and represent the shareholder role in the corporation’s power and capital structure.  Further, the equity trustee could recommend CEO candidates who could then be approved by shareholder vote.  The equity trustee would monitor the CEO with the help of the other board members.  The shareholders’ ability to remove or replace the CEO could have a significant effect on corporate governance.  The shareholders’ power would have to be balanced against the rest of the board’s role in monitoring management.

While significantly different in structure from the current regime, this change in the exercise of shareholder authority would not represent a revolutionary departure from current practices.  The choice of a corporation’s CEO is not free from investor influence now.  Creditors are able to pressure boards to remove and replace CEOs when corporations are in trouble.[127]  The creditors play an active role in monitoring the CEO.[128]  Giving shareholders power over who serves as CEO seems fitting given the power over corporate managers shareholders currently enjoy.  When the corporation is healthy, shareholders are responsible for monitoring the board, and the board is supposed to monitor and hire or replace the CEO with the shareholders’ interests in corporate wealth maximization in mind.[129]  It makes sense, then, to give shareholders more power over who serves as the CEO as a replacement for their power to choose board members if the current board structure is removed or replaced.

One possible way to balance the relevant interests and provide for some stability in management is to allow shareholders to elect the CEO at particular intervals, but to only allow removal of a CEO with a vote by the rest of the board or on account of defined “cause.”  If a CEO is doing a bad job, then the board should agree that his performance is subpar and a vote for removal should be successful.  Removal for specifically defined cause can protect a company from a particularly harmful CEO.  Even if other investors want to remove a CEO and are able to vote to remove or are able to pressure the shareholders to move for a change, the shareholders would choose the replacement—thus the shareholders retain primary control over that part of corporate management.

This exercise of authority replaces the power shareholders now have to elect the board of directors.  In fact, the power they exercise could have a more direct bearing on corporate management and decision making than they now have—shareholders would be able to exercise that power more effectively and directly through a sophisticated, informed representative.  Of course, the parties could reach one of any number of agreements about how to balance the power each constituent can wield over management personnel.  One of this Article’s objectives is to encourage such negotiation so that the constituents of each corporation find the right arrangements for their firm.

While the proposed regime would change some of the process of corporate decision making, the reality of power relationships would remain largely the same.  The CEO is already beholden to various investors and serves at the pleasure of the board, which purports to represent shareholder interests.  With an investor board, the board of directors replicates the monitoring relationships already extant in the modern corporation: creditors monitor through their loan covenants, labor unions enforce their collective bargaining agreements, and both groups have the ability to seek removal of the CEO if their rights are particularly compromised.  Still, a replacement CEO cannot be appointed without the approval of shareholder “representatives”—the modern board.[130]  In the new scheme, the replacement CEO would be chosen by more direct shareholder representatives responsible only for pursuing the interests of shareholder wealth maximization—without the current boards’ sympathy for management and with the advantages of a better understanding of the company.  This understanding would come from the closer monitoring a shareholder representative could provide because an equity trustee would devote more time and resources to representing shareholders in its portfolio of companies.

B.            Why a Post-Board Firm is an Improvement

An advantage of using a collection of active investors at the top of the corporate hierarchy is that it approximates the way corporate decisions are made and so provides a structure for more direct and meaningful accountability for corporate decision making.  Corporate law places such an emphasis on the role of the board of directors, and places so much responsibility and accountability on the board’s shoulders, that it may divert resources from understanding relationships that have more of a bearing on corporate decision making.  Bringing together the most effective board-monitoring parties should decrease the costs of corporate monitoring and decision making and should also highlight the parties responsible for particular decisions so that they can be held accountable for the jobs they are supposed to do.

An investor board would be better at monitoring than the traditional board because investors are not as sympathetic to management and so have the necessary distance from management to monitor more effectively.[131]  An investor board would also better perform the board’s management function because investors who closely monitor the corporation must understand the state of the corporation’s affairs to protect their own interests.  Additionally, investors already form opinions about the major decisions that should be made on the corporation’s behalf.  Of course, these opinions may diverge because of individual interests the board members have that conflict with those of the corporation.  For this reason, an investor board would represent a significant departure from the laws and norms underlying the structure of the modern corporate board and thus would require changes to the legal framework governing corporate management.  Nevertheless, because the recommended structure more accurately approximates actual decision making, it can provide for more predictable, meaningful accountability and do a better job of performing the limited functions of the modern board.

1. Better at Monitoring

An investor board would do a better job of monitoring management than the modern board of directors because the investor representatives would be more socially and, for the most part, professionally independent from management than current board members.  An investor board could, therefore, provide the kind of hierarchical monitoring that second-guesses the subject’s judgment that the board of directors is ideally supposed to provide for the corporation’s management team.  The professionals serving on the investor board would not be officers at other companies.  Rather, they would be responsible for representing the interests of those seeking to protect the expectations of certain investments.  Therefore, they do better professionally if there is more rigorous monitoring of corporate managers, rather than less, because the investors choosing them for their positions will evaluate them based on the job they do protecting those investors.  Most important, unlike current officers or directors,[132] they would not be setting a reciprocal precedent for the monitoring to which they would be subject themselves.

One caveat applies to the claim that investor representatives would be professionally independent from management.  In some instances, the corporation chooses which banks it borrows money from or may hire institutional shareholders to manage firm retirement funds[133] and so, in those circumstances, the corporation would be choosing the investors who would sit on the board.  When parties serving on the investor board depend on the corporation for business, they rely on good relationships with corporate managers.  In those instances, the investors themselves may want to curry favor with management so that they will continue to be selected by the firm.  Such conflicts have proven problematic for auditors in the past—auditors were responsible for independently reviewing corporate financial records, but relied on the managers whose work they were reviewing for business.[134]

Additional protections should be available in a post-board firm to prevent those conflicts from presenting a problem.  For example, the selection of creditors, at least private lenders, should be dominated by the terms of the loan.  Other corporate monitors can ensure that that this takes place and can also provide a check against the conflicted interests of any one investor.  Investor representative sympathies for managers would only be a serious problem if management selected a significant portion of the investors represented on the board.  In those instances, the selection of private lenders could be done with the advice and consent of other board members.  That way, allegiance to management would not be an effective way to maintain the relationship with the firm and the company may proceed on the merits of service offered by the investor or investor representative in question.

These potential conflicts of interest are easier to see and thus easier to guard against than those arising from the empathies plaguing the current board structure.  Investor representatives, by the very nature of their job descriptions (as zealous representatives of reasonably attentive investors[135]), would be less likely to feel sympathetic to management.  Investor representatives already monitor management on their clients’ behalf,[136] by enforcing loan covenants, for example, and do so without problematic allegiance to management.[137]  The dynamics of those relationships between investor representatives and managers should not change by simply elevating the monitoring the representatives do to a more formally recognized place in the corporate governance structure.

Investor representatives would also enjoy an informational advantage over the directors on a modern monitoring board.  Recall that board positions are not full-time jobs.  Most directors have very demanding careers apart from their service on corporate boards.[138]  They simply cannot stay informed about corporate business on a regular basis and must be brought up to speed quickly when it is time to make significant decisions.  Because they are already monitoring the management of relevant companies, investor representatives are paying attention to important information affecting their clients’ investments in a number of firms.  In this way, investor representatives could resemble the professional outside directors suggested by Professors Gilson and Kraakman.[139]  Each new board member would have a portfolio of companies on whose board she sits, and she could devote most of her professional energy to reviewing the information necessary to monitor those companies.

Investor board members would not focus solely on the information necessary to make management decisions or monitor managers.  Most important would be the information the investor must have to enforce its contracts with the corporation.  It is the enforcement of those contracts with the firm that constitutes most of the monitoring of management and most of the new corporate governance structure suggested here.  Monitoring that is driven by individual contracts with the firm can be more predictable for the managers being monitored, making the parameters of their jobs clearer.  The scope of investment contracts and the powers assigned under them also make the powers of monitors over management and the firm more transparent.

This contract-driven scheme resembles governance through “‘Big Boy’ letters” described by Professors Baird and Henderson.[140]  Baird and Henderson suggest that corporate governance by fiduciary duties owed to shareholders is an outdated notion and that sophisticated parties should be able to negotiate ex ante about the responsibilities they want to enforce against the firm’s managers.[141]  They then argue that courts should honor those agreements and that those agreements should in turn shape managers’ duties.[142]  In a corporate governance system dominated by contracts, those with an interest in how the corporation is performing and with interests to protect are paying close attention to corporate management with some, but not too many, means of responding to managerial decision making.  They are able to monitor one another, and each party’s rights, responsibilities, and powers are known to the others.  The enforcement of these contracts yields the most meaningful monitoring in corporate governance.[143]  That is why I propose bringing those relationships to the forefront of corporate governance and why I think that kind of monitoring is superior to the monitoring provided by an independent board of directors.  Bringing the focus more accurately to the parties doing the real governance work should improve our ability to hold the responsible parties accountable for corporate decision making and should make the decision-making structure more transparent and accessible.  It illuminates an important part of the corporate decision-making structure.

2. Better at Management

Because investors are often better informed than members of an independent monitoring board, and because investor representatives already play an important role in corporate decision making, an investor board, or a less formal group of investors, would also do a better job of performing the management function assigned to the board.  Investor representatives often know much more about the day-to-day operation of the business and the state of its capital structure than do monitoring boards, so they are in a better position to make major decisions.[144]  If asked to perform the board’s functions, investors would come into a decision with their own opinions about information acquired from officers as part of the monitoring and enforcement of their contractual relationships, so much of the information on which they would base decisions would not be presented to them immediately before deliberations on a particular question.  Further, the presentation of the information would not necessarily be shaded toward whatever outcome management preferred.[145]

One potential problem with giving investors control over corporate decision making is that they may have interests or other investments that conflict with the “best” course of action for the corporation.  Various investors may have differing risk preferences and may want to influence corporate management to honor their preferences in making business decisions for the company.[146]  A group of creditors could conspire to vote together to exercise control over the company to try to force it to take actions consistent with their creditors’ selfish interests.  This concern arises any time parties with potentially conflicted interests have decision-making authority.  This problem is considered in more detail below.[147]  For now, it is worthwhile to point out that there are several reasons it need not be an intractable problem and that those interested relationships may actually provide important advantages.

The board’s decision-making authority is extremely limited, so to the extent we are finding an alternative way to make those decisions, we are talking about a very limited universe of corporate decision making.  Combine the limits of the board’s decision-making authority with the ability of these investor representatives to influence daily decision making in more direct ways, and it is difficult to see how imputing current board responsibilities to the investor representatives would create a new problem or exacerbate an old one.  To the extent the board’s “independence” and lack of conflicted interest helps it represent shareholders, the shareholders of a company with an investor board would be more effectively and directly represented and have a greater ability to negotiate with the other investors who may compromise their current interests.  Replacing the monitoring board with one that more closely represents the corporate decision-making process serves largely to remove a vestigial middleman of sorts from the appropriate balancing of the financial interests that make up the modern corporation.

3. Contractual Accountability

Transitioning to an investor board would also enhance accountability for corporate decision making.  For instance, enforcement of investment contracts may be a better way to hold managers accountable to investors of all kinds than reliance on fiduciary duties has proved to be.[148]  Baird and Henderson suggest enforcing disclosure requirements against managers through ex ante provisions in investment contracts.[149]  That way, managers are responsible for making sure the corporation abides by disclosure requirements to various parties in interest.  Having received the required disclosures, the investors or corporate constituents in question could protect their other rights against the corporation.[150]  They need managers to make the proper disclosures to enforce their contracts, so it makes sense to hold managers personally responsible for faithfully providing important information about the business.[151]  Further, disclosure is a discreet and specific task that is relatively transparent thus investors will be able to reliably determine whether managers have complied.

Similar terms may be effective beyond disclosure requirements.  To the extent there are specific tasks managers can perform, investors can require them to do so and enforce those requirements contractually.  If managers cause breaches—with a certain predetermined degree of malfeasance—they can be subject to personal penalties or consequences as provided in investor agreements with the firm.  This would allow all corporate constituents to enforce their agreements with the firm and to hold managers personally responsible only for certain, specific obligations.  This prevents uncertainty for managers by delineating their responsibilities and limits the power of individual constituents over the firm and its management in ways other parties in interest can count on.

For instance, shareholders know exactly what power creditors would have over management under particular circumstances and could account for that power in deciding the best course of action.  As suggested above, the power to remove the CEO would belong to an investor board, or to a group of qualified investors, only under certain circumstances.  But if the CEO is removed, all shareholders would have the power to choose a replacement, keeping in mind that their choice should not be completely inimical to the preferences of creditors and other investors.  If shareholders do too much to compromise the interests of other investors, those investors may be unwilling to cooperate when deciding how to avail themselves of their rights against the corporation.

The success of a post-board governance structure relies upon carefully balanced rights and responsibilities among the parties in power, with full disclosure and knowledge of what those rights and powers are and how they may be exercised.  Its strength lies in the ability of the relevant parties to openly discuss what actions they might take to direct the course of the corporation’s business and what decisions each may make when confronted with important choices.  It brings the balancing act that current directors and officers must perform in their heads out into the open and allows for direct bargaining among the parties in interest.

The notion of managerial accountability under an investor board is very different from the traditional norm of relying upon fiduciary duties in corporate governance.  Currently, corporate governance relies heavily upon a fiduciary rhetoric that emphasizes an obligation for directors to run the corporation according to shareholders’ best interests.[152]  The rhetoric is often hollow and rarely leads to serious liability, basically eviscerating any threat of personal liability officers and directors might face.[153]  The choice Delaware courts have made—to not enforce fiduciary duties with personal liability—shows a wariness of using liability as a means to discipline corporate decision makers.[154]  Holding managers accountable through specific contract terms allows more predictable, meaningful liability.  This makes particular sense in the context of an investor board.  There, board members would only be accountable directly to the investors they represent.  Board members want to ensure that managers uphold the bargains the investors have made with the corporation, but only want other investors to be able to exercise clearly-defined powers over management.  In maintaining the proper balance among investors, it is crucial that all board members understand the powers of others as well as when and how those powers may be exercised.  Precise contract terms help to provide that certainty.

4. Leaving Fiduciary Duties Behind

Delaware corporate law relies heavily on fiduciary duties to address agency costs in the large, public corporation.[155]  What is lost in a purely contractual—as opposed to fiduciary—corporate governance regime is the ability to apply more flexible standards and decide ex post what constitutes a breach of the obligation to manage the corporation in the interests of corporate wealth maximization, or, more specifically, to avoid conflicts of interest that compromise a director or officer’s ability to decide what is in the corporation’s best interests.[156]  That loss would not be so great once one considers the fact that the protection afforded by fiduciary duties, outside the social-norm-creating benefits of the rhetoric, is not substantial and the costs associated with misunderstanding the extent of the legal protection provided by fiduciary duties may be significant.[157]  Those norms can arise without the pretense of supposed liability that results in significant wasted time, litigation expense, and legislative angst.  Vague liability rules do not have a place in corporate governance.

One concern about using vague liability rules has been the potential chilling effect of unpredictable personal monetary liability for officers and directors.[158]  We rely on corporate decision makers to exercise business judgment and hope that they will cause the corporation to make investment decisions reflecting a desirable level of risk.[159]  If those decision makers are afraid of being held personally liable for decisions deemed bad in hindsight, then they will likely not take profitable risks.[160]  The business judgment rule protects corporate decision makers from liability for what turn out to be bad business decisions, leaving conflicts of interest as the only reliable basis for personal liability under Delaware corporate law.[161]

That does not mean that corporate investors are powerless in the face of bad decision makers.  Bad decision makers are supposed to be replaced or punished (i.e., paid less than good decision makers).  The current corporate governance model provides officers and directors a great deal of job security.  Directors are generally only removed when they are not reelected in annual elections.[162]  Officers generally have to be removed by directors who tend to be sympathetic to the officers they have chosen because they do not want to admit that they have done a poor job of appointing or monitoring senior managers.[163]  Creditors have enjoyed some success in causing senior officers to be replaced but are only able to do so in the most dire of financial circumstances.[164]  In fact, a great deal of officer turnover occurs when a firm is experiencing severe financial difficulty,[165] but officer positions tend to be secure most of the time and are often otherwise protected by lucrative golden parachutes.[166]

In a post-board firm, officers may enjoy fewer protections and key decision makers may be easier to remove.  For one, investor representatives are directly accountable to those with interests in the firm and those who are actively monitoring their performance.  The officers who make the day-to-day decisions must report regularly to investor representatives in a manner prescribed by the investor contracts with the firm.  The CEO may be removed by the board, but is chosen at regular intervals by shareholder representatives.  This would allow investors to weigh in if they think the CEO is doing a bad job, but leaves the residual claimant the ultimate authority to choose the CEO.  Furthermore, reduced dependence on vague liability rules should mean that investors will remove officers who are performing poorly and officers will, in turn, work to build strong reputations for making profitable, wise decisions for their firms.  The enhanced monitoring provided by the investor board, and the ability investors will have to enforce particular contract terms, will mean that officers’ decisions are more carefully monitored and so can be more accurately evaluated.

Of course, any monitoring and accountability provided should not exceed efficient levels.  Stephen Bainbridge adopts Kenneth Arrow’s view of the relationship between authority and accountability in defending board primacy.[167]  Bainbridge points out that accountability cannot be so great that it overwhelms the authority the board is given to make business decisions for the firm.[168]  Second-guessing every board decision essentially robs the board of its authority and gives it to the parties that can hold the board accountable.[169]  The same concern would arise in a post-board firm to the extent officers may be held accountable for the business decisions they make or other corporate constituents could be held accountable for exceeding the bounds of their authority in making decisions for the firm.  Someone has to have authority to make business decisions and that authority cannot be second-guessed or overturned constantly.  Nothing about a post-board firm’s governance structure, as described here, undermines the business judgment rule or a deference to business decisions made by officers with technical knowledge of the firm’s business.  The accountability this Article encourages focuses on responding to existing violations of governance rules and norms rather than concentrating on defining new ones.  The idea is to hold managers who defraud investors directly accountable, not to limit the activities or discretion of honest managers.

5. Summary

A post-board firm would be run by its managers and representatives of major corporate investors and constituents according to a well-balanced system of contracts.  The investor representatives would fulfill the board’s monitoring role, while the officers would make management decisions subject to the rights and powers of significant parties in interest.  Investors thus empowered would be better at performing both board functions.  They have the independence necessary to be good monitors and the intimate knowledge of the corporation to be capable corporate decision makers.  Problems with conflicts of interest would be different, but not greater than, those faced by current monitoring boards and could be overcome through carefully negotiated and enforced contracts.  Investors would be able to strike a sensible balance of power directly by negotiating various rights and powers with the corporation and enforcing those as necessary, then negotiating with each other when the time comes for concerted decision making.

D.            Problematic Relationships in a Post-Board Firm

The most apparent potential problem with using an investor board as the dominant monitoring and decision-making body for a corporation involves managing the negotiation dynamics of the various parties.  How would various investor representatives interact?  Would they behave strategically to form coalitions to take power from other investors?  Would we allow creditors to exercise too much control over a healthy company?  How do we really moderate shareholder views, particularly as the views of various shareholders may differ?  Might more than one shareholder representative be necessary?  What do we do with divergent views and risk preferences?  Who wins?  What if the “wrong” party wins? We have long counted on the board of directors to mediate these disputes, break these ties, and fill these gaps.

Despite having a board to referee these interactions, these very questions have long plagued corporate governance.  Tomes have been devoted to determining whose interests should drive corporate decision making at different points in the corporation’s life.[170]  How the interests of corporate constituents should be balanced is an important question that dominates the board’s decision making under the current system.[171]  Allowing investors to assume the board’s role would not necessarily end these inquiries about the struggle for corporate control, but there is also little reason to believe that an investor board should make it more difficult to reach satisfactory answers or to find the right balance of power over corporate governance.  In fact, a post-board governance structure would allow each corporation to decide its optimal balance of power according to who its significant investors are and what interests motivate its business decisions.

In thinking about how dominant investors in a post-board firm would interact with each other, it is important to acknowledge that the board has limited power.  The board of directors is only charged with making a few significant decisions for the firm and is mostly concerned with monitoring the CEO and other senior managers.[172]  By shifting those roles to investors, we would simply be acknowledging more directly the monitoring and managing investors already do.  It does not add much to that authority to ask those investors to participate in decisions currently reserved for the board of directors.  Instead of giving the keys to the corporation to investors in a new way, we would be bringing investors’ power over the board’s limited decision-making authority out into the open.  The power investors can exercise over management outside of the board decision-making structure dwarfs the ability of the board to make business decisions for the firm.  Giving the board’s power to investors should not be cause for too much concern.

In the same vein, to the extent we worry that improvident alliances among various corporate constituents, to the exclusion of others, would undermine corporate priorities and the ability to reach decisions that are in the best interest of corporate wealth maximization, we should already be worried about such alliances.  Currently, creditors can form coalitions or coordinate with each other in the enforcement of their covenants.[173]  In fact, that is exactly what the bankruptcy system encourages.  The basic rules and structures of that system often bleed into pre-bankruptcy times of financial distress as creditors work with the debtor firm to arrive at accommodations that will allow the company to stay afloat.[174]  All of that work and negotiation is done to the practical exclusion of shareholders[175] and may or may not involve the concerns of other corporate constituents, depending on how vital those constituents are to the firm’s survival.  It is hard to see why creditors would take such an interest in the management of the firm if the firm is not either financially distressed or at risk of becoming so.  Enhanced powers over management when the firm is healthy are not reserved to creditors in the creditors’ contracts.

One may argue that by including creditors in post-board governance we allow them to cast meaningful votes about corporate decisions even when the firm is healthy.  That is not necessarily true if we define creditors’ roles in similar terms as we do now—that is, empowering them to influence corporate management only when the firm is experiencing financial distress.  To the extent a post-board firm does give creditors some power during times of financial health, creditors’ preferences should not diverge so widely from those of other investors in those instances.  It may be true that creditors disfavor riskier corporate business strategies and that their preferences differ from shareholders’ in that regard.[176]  However, it makes sense to limit creditors’ voting power during times of financial health and enhance it during times of financial distress, just as we currently do with creditor power provided in loan agreements.  Nothing about a post-board governance structure prevents such an accommodation—rather, the proposed structure encourages just that sort of balance.

Furthermore, we must think carefully about the possible effects of inappropriate collusion before we believe it is a significant problem.  Why would a creditor want to take time to run the company in a way the creditor sees fit unless the company is in serious financial trouble?  Using too heavy a hand when it could cause a corporation to be less profitable might cause corporations to disfavor a particular creditor in the future, which, in turn, might cause those creditors to lose business.  Additionally, excessive control by investors that hinders effective or profitable management of the firm may cause a corporation to lose good managers.  Similar problems could arise with shareholders who decide to use whatever authority they have to pursue short-term gain.  No one shareholder has absolute authority over the shareholder position and shareholders still have to assert their will through the decisions of officers and are still checked to some extent by the firm’s contracts with other investors and the power creditors have over corporate governance.  If shareholders push a management agenda that is too risky or that is ineffective, creditors stand ready to assert the considerable authority they would have in times of financial distress.

In a post-board governance regime, it would be easier to see collusive or potentially troublesome activities of corporate investors, bringing their management and monitoring activities into the open.  That would allow the firm to balance its contracts as necessary and would allow constituents with differing interests to check each other.  For now, it is important to set up the necessary safety nets to ensure that no one party has the power to dominate the firm (without buying that kind of control) and that no one investor can usurp corporate authority to the detriment of the firm or other investors.  It will take time to figure out what those agreements and relationships should look like and how they should be structured.

In the meantime, we should do what we can to remove obstacles to what may be a very beneficial and effective evolution of the board of directors.  If we remove legal obstacles that are not essential to useful functioning of the board and put in their place appropriate protective rules that provide more flexibility, then we may realize a deliberate evolution of the corporate governance structure to one that more accurately reflects the realities of corporate decision making.[177]  This strategy should lead to better monitoring and management and also a more effective way to hold those in charge accountable for performing their jobs faithfully and as expected.

The proposal set forth in this Article is intentionally nonspecific.  My intention is not to present a “new board in a box” to which one could add water and have a fully formed new corporate governance system.  I only intend to suggest a path toward what may be natural evolution for corporate governance so that we can see what agreements the relevant parties reach.  I think, in many important ways, the market has already begun work on this by changing the power structure of corporate decision making so as to render the monitoring board very weak.  The next step may be to remove corporate law’s focus on the independent monitoring board so that better governance structures may emerge in its place.  The next Part explains how to begin to do that so that the natural evolution of corporate governance may continue.

III.  Potential Obstacles

Any time someone suggests an innovation in corporate law, the first question posed to challenge the innovation is bound to be, “If it’s such a good idea, why hasn’t it happened already?”  Market forces have been at work on the best way to run a business for hundreds of years and the corporation has grown and changed dramatically in its history.[178]  We have reasons for the corporate governance structures we have chosen, and disturbing those carefully considered choices should be done cautiously and must be justified thoroughly.  If the current board structure is a product of rational market forces and wise choices over the course of generations, then those in favor of changing it drastically may face an uphill battle.

I argue that the changes to the current structure of the board of directors proposed by this Article reflect rather than upend the work market choices have done on corporate governance.  Corporate governance has evolved to the point that corporate constituents and officers exercise more power over the firm than the board, and to the point where the board of directors performs only the most superficial monitoring and is called upon to make few business decisions under the strong influence of the corporation’s officers whom they are charged with monitoring.  The weak position of the board in its very limited role is a product of market evolution, as is the strength of the influence of significant corporate creditors and the influence parties like proxy advisors and some institutional shareholders can have over corporate governance.  The law, not the market, preserves the place of the board of directors in corporate governance.

Market evolution has led us to a corporate governance structure that resembles the investor board suggested here.  To move formally to such a board, several intermediate steps are necessary.  First, legal impediments to the evolution of boards in this direction will have to be removed.  Then, we might find an intermediate step with an advisory board of investor representatives.  That might be a way to gather investor representatives in the same place so they can begin conferring with each other and pooling their monitoring abilities and information.  If they come together to advise and monitor the board, albeit in a nonbinding way, then the relationships may begin to evolve such that the “advisory” board replaces the traditional board of directors.  My goal in this Article is to set the stage for a new (and, I think better) way of constituting a corporate board and to argue that we should clear the way for corporate governance to evolve toward such a change.

Allowing corporate governance to evolve toward an investor board, and, eventually, the elimination of the board of directors, would require removing legal impediments to that evolution.  Rules mandating board independence would have to be relaxed, as would interpretations of prohibited conflicts of interest.  For instance, the investors dominating a post-board governance structure will necessarily be buying and selling the corporation’s securities while they or their representatives have access to material, nonpublic information.  Such conflicts would have to determine the extent to which certain parties could participate in corporate decision making and may result in additional requirements for pre-trading disclosures.

Certain laws relating to corporate governance would have to change to lower the barriers to this kind of evolution.  Lowering those barriers could result in some unintended consequences, and we should be careful not to remove the protections we have against opportunistic or self-interested behavior on the part of officers and directors that could harm the firm.  The emphasis here should be on removing or relaxing regulations that are not actually helpful or that constrain the evolution of corporate governance in unhelpful ways.  From there, any changes to that structure would have to develop slowly and carefully and perhaps reflect the needs of individual firms.  This last Part highlights ways those paths to evolution may be cleared and to suggest possible forms that evolution could take.

A.            Mandatory Board Structure

We might not have yet fully evolved to the governance structure suggested by this Article because state and federal law mandate some aspects of corporate governance.  Right now, the vast majority of corporations cannot dispense with the board of directors entirely because, under Delaware law, the corporation must be operated under the direction and supervision of a board of directors.[179]  Investors and their direct representatives cannot make up a majority of a corporation’s board because public companies must have majority independent boards: a majority of board members cannot have personal or financial ties to the firm.[180]  None of the members of an investor board would satisfy this definition of independence because officers would work for the company and the investor representatives would be working to directly represent the interests of those having financial ties to the corporation.  The Sarbanes-Oxley Act requires the boards of public companies to form audit and compensation committees made up of independent board members.[181]  These statutory and regulatory provisions mandate a corporate governance structure for public companies that an investor board would violate.

The application of common law principles of corporate governance would also have to be adjusted to accommodate the lack of board independence.  For instance, the application of the duty of loyalty to the corporate board would have to be tweaked to accommodate directors representing those with financial interests in the firm and interests that might diverge with those of the corporation.  The investor representatives would have to disclose their trading activities and interests they have that may be adverse to the corporation so that their decision-making authority can be altered accordingly.  Allowing investor board members to continue to trade in the corporation’s securities (trading that defines their board membership in many instances) would also require accommodations in the application of insider trading laws.  This Part addresses these regulatory obstacles and argues that some should be removed while others could be supplemented by special rules regulating the conflicts of interest affecting investor board members.

1. The Board “Requirement”

Delaware corporate law provides that:

The business and affairs of every corporation organized under this chapter shall be managed by or under the direction of a board of directors, except as may be otherwise provided in this chapter or in its certificate of incorporation.  If such a provision is made in the certificate of incorporation, the powers and duties conferred or imposed upon the board of directors in this chapter shall be exercised or performed to such extent and by such persons as shall be provided in the certificate of incorporation.[182]

The common understanding of this provision is that it requires that each corporation organized under Delaware law have a board of directors.[183]  To the extent the language in section 141(a) allows a firm to provide for a different governance structure, it has generally been interpreted to refer to the power of boards to delegate their authority to committees[184] or officers[185] in certain circumstances.  Nevertheless, section 141(a) is, strictly speaking, a default rule that corporations can contract around in their articles of incorporation.[186]

Thinking of section 141(a) as a default rule might provide an avenue through which corporations could evolve to post-board governance without overturning state incorporation statutes.[187]  Lynn Stout points out that corporations are free to adopt any number of governance structures at the outset, yet public companies have failed to do so.[188]  In fact, public firms and those preparing for IPOs have adopted provisions that strengthen board power vis-á-vis shareholders and hostile bidders.[189]  It is easy to see that the reasons for preferring a strong board of directors have little to do with regard for board decision making and are more likely driven by the fact that the choice is framed as one between giving dispersed, rationally apathetic, and unsophisticated shareholders power over corporate decision making or leaving that power vested in a board.[190]  If that is the choice, indeed board authority is the prudent course of action.  It is not realistic to frame the market choice as one between corporations with boards of directors and those without, because all public corporations have a board of directors.[191]  The infrastructure necessary to allow the elimination of the board in a large, public corporation is not yet in place.

That is why this Article suggests how we could allow the market to slowly move toward a post-board governance structure and does not propose that corporations eliminate boards of directors immediately.  Before the board of directors can be responsibly eliminated, better mechanisms for shareholder representation would have to be in place.  The governance structure of public corporations would have to change slowly.  Perhaps significant investors could begin by forming an advisory committee to more directly communicate with each other while monitoring management and influencing significant corporate decisions.  Then, perhaps that advisory board could take over for the monitoring board of directors.  Finally, the formal board structure could give way to a strong system of investor contracts.  Too abrupt a change would not be beneficial for corporations or investors, so it is inappropriate to take a measure of market preferences in the current regime as a signal of what may happen if market evolution is allowed to take its natural course.  There are still significant obstacles to the evolution away from the board and those legal obstacles must be removed to allow corporations to design the governance structure that best suits their needs.

That freedom is contemplated by state incorporation statutes that provide default terms around which organizing corporations can contract.  Where state law allows freedom to design firm-specific governance structures, the laws governing public companies place far more onerous requirements forcing firms to adopt more uniform governance regimes.  Where state law allows corporations to opt out of a governance structure dominated by a board of directors, federal law seems to prohibit that choice.  That is not to suggest that there is no role for federal regulation of public companies, only that state law has the right idea—adopt default rules that provide certain minimum protections from abuse, and let the parties design the form that works best for their company.

2. Regulations Requiring Independence

The New York Stock Exchange Listed Company Manual requires that listed companies have a board composed of a majority of independent directors.[192]  This would seem to rule out a listed company’s not having a board of directors at all and further defines what the composition of that board should be.  The listing requirements define an independent director as one having a “material relationship” with the listed company.[193]  A comment to the apposite section explains that “material relationship” is to be interpreted broadly and cannot be specifically defined, but would include “commercial, industrial, banking, consulting, legal, accounting, charitable and familial relationships, among others.”[194]  This would seem to pose a problem for an investor board as all members would either be managers or investors in the firm.  Creditors would have “commercial” or “banking” relationships with the listed company.

However, the comment clarifies that it means “independence from management,” thus holding a large amount of stock would not necessarily make a board member “not independent.”[195]  That would seem to solve the problem and emphasize that the NYSE intended for boards to exercise their judgment—that as long as the investor did not have ties to managers, it might qualify as “independent.”  The regulation does not say “no material relationship with the listed company’s managers,” however, so it seems that those doing business with the firm or investing with the firm would not be considered independent board members.  A board made up entirely of those investors having “commercial” and “banking” relationships “with the company” and senior managers would not pass the independence requirement.  Because the comment explaining the requirement leaves the door to “independent” board members with financial interests in the firm, and the rule is framed broadly and in a way designed to allow discretion, it may not be difficult to adjust the rule to more clearly allow significant investor representation on the board of directors of a listed company.

Sarbanes-Oxley[196] requires that public companies have independent audit[197] and compensation committees.[198]  The committees are to be made up of members of the company’s board of directors who are “independent.”[199]  Again, these regulations so strongly assume that public corporations have a board of directors that they practically require that public companies have a board even though state law does not.  Furthermore, independence is not specifically defined, but contemplates members who would not be personally interested in the decisions assigned to the committee[200]—decisions relating to executive compensation and reviewing the work of the firm’s outside auditors.  Many investor representatives would be able to satisfy the independence requirements for the compensation and audit committees even if they would not qualify as independent directors for the purposes of satisfying the listing requirements.  Thus, part of the evolution proposed by this Article could take place under current Sarbanes-Oxley rules, thereby maintaining the protections those federal regulations provide, while the governance structure moves slowly away from the board-centric model.  Then, as firms evolve beyond the use of a board of directors, federal law may have to be tweaked to accommodate the change.

Congress cannot be accused of inventing corporate governance reforms that were out of step with corporate practice at the time they were adopted.  As described above, the market had evolved to favor the use of independent monitoring boards.[201]  The problem is that the regulations requiring the use of increasingly independent monitoring boards of directors artificially stalls that evolution.  The problems with the independent monitoring board have become apparent and each new regulation makes it harder for corporate governance to continue to evolve past the current ineffective board structure.  To the extent regulations force corporate governance to maintain ineffective or meaningless structures, they impose costs and prevent the market from correcting problems it discovers.[202]  Corporate governance has long been considered the province of the states because state law allows firms to adjust their governance structures to suit their particular needs and allows those structures to evolve over time.[203]

B.            Laws Governing Conflicts of Interest

Because directors are supposed to exercise independent judgment about which business decisions are in the best interests of the firm, corporate law focuses on ensuring that they do not place personal interest ahead of firm interest in their work for the corporation.  The fiduciary duty of loyalty prohibits conflicts of interest and self-dealing that compromise the corporation’s wealth.[204]  The federal prohibition of insider trading builds on the fiduciary duty of loyalty imposed by state law.[205]  It prohibits an officer or director’s trading of a corporation’s securities while in possession of material, nonpublic corporate information.[206]  The rationale for the insider trading prohibition is that corporate executives are supposed to use corporate information for the benefit of the firm, not for personal profit.[207]  They breach their duty of loyalty by trading on that information without first disclosing it to the market.[208]

In a post-board firm whose governance is dominated by investor representatives, it will be more difficult to separate investors’ individual interests from the work they do for the firm.  Their individual interests define their role with the firm and place them in their positions of relative power.  In fact, the representation of those individual interests makes investor representatives effective monitors and gives them the incentives to invest in the information necessary to make business judgments for the firm.  Conflicts of interest may pose a different sort of problem in a post-board firm that is regulated by contractual relationships rather than broad fiduciary duties.

The key to overcoming the difficulties associated with moving investors representing individual interests into the firm’s dominant decision-making roles is to understand that a post-board firm contemplates a different governance structure in significant ways.  First, the powers various investors exercise would vary depending on their contracts with the firm.  Different investors would have the power to influence different decisions to varying degrees.  This is in stark contrast to the current board structure that assumes that directors exercise equal authority when making corporate decision as a collective body.  An investment board, and eventually, a post-board governance structure, would make major corporate decisions by consulting the various parties in interest who have the power to influence a particular decision.  Again, that may be drawing on the fact of individual interests that may conflict with the best interests of the firm.  But, with just a few parties in interest at the table, the potentially conflicting interests of each will be more transparent.  Those conflicts can be managed the way director conflicts are now: with disclosure and appropriate modification of the relevant party’s decision-making power.

Regulating insider trading among investors whose trading defines their management authority within the firm and who will have access to substantial, perhaps nonpublic, information about the firm could present challenges.  Insider trading by investors represented in a post-board firm’s governance regime could be addressed in a number of ways.  In regulating insider trading in a post-board firm, we may draw on insights from the regulation of officer and director trading now.  Officers and directors are currently prohibited from trading on material nonpublic information and firms often set certain blackout dates defined by the release of certain corporate information during which officers and directors cannot trade in the corporation’s securities.[209]  In a post-board firm, certain investors may be banned from trading in the corporation’s securities, or derivatives based on the value of the corporation’s securities, while charged with authority to make corporate decisions.  Furthermore, regulations prohibiting investor representatives from sharing certain nonpublic information with their clients may be justified.  To the extent investor rights in a post-board firm mirror the rights influential investors have now, their trading should not present new problems.  If investors have access to more information in a post-board firm, securities law can adapt to address the insider trading risks those investors pose in the same ways it responded to the threat of officer and director trading.

Conclusion

The board of directors has become a vestigial entity that is structurally unable to achieve its intended purposes.  Many reforms have tried to tweak its structure to improve it, but those very reforms have made it even less meaningful and less effective.  Boards are both too independent to be good managers and not independent enough to be good monitors.  In the face of a weak board of directors, other corporate actors have taken a more active role in monitoring management and influencing important business decisions.  A firm’s investors and other influential constituents use their contract rights against the firm to influence management and monitor management more carefully than the board can to protect their interests and investments in the firm.

Because these corporate constituents can do the board’s job more effectively than can the current board, the formal corporate governance structure must evolve to reflect the realities of corporate decision making.  The corporate board of directors should be comprised of investor representatives and, for some purposes, corporate officers so that the parties that do the most to monitor management and decide the course of the corporation’s business can negotiate openly about how to balance and exercise their power over corporate decision making.  Changing the formal structure this way would focus attention and accountability on the actors responsible for corporate decision making.  Transparency that reveals how corporate decisions are really made—and who makes them—should improve that decision making by increasing accountability for those decisions.  We would be able to see who exercises what authority and so would not waste time, money, and energy trying to hold independent board members responsible for decisions they did not know about and could not have controlled.  In time, firms may move away from a formal board structure entirely, allowing the network of investor contracts and the interaction of those parties with management to perform the functions once delegated to the board of directors.

This Article does not offer a detailed description of what post-board firm should look like or what the investors’ contracts should provide.  Rather, it suggests that we allow corporate governance to evolve further down the path it has chosen.  The realities of corporate decision making reflect important choices by knowledgeable market participants.  We should remove obstacles that keep us from formalizing that reality.  A post-board governance structure would reflect a real change in corporate governance and the way we think about and implement management authority over a corporation.  It is impossible to say now exactly how that change should happen or what exactly it should look like because it should be the product of a careful and slow development informed by an appreciation of what structures best serve the needs of companies.  To suppose that the world of corporate investment has changed drastically in the last one hundred years[210] and that the governance structure of the firm has not or should not change at all is nonsensical.  Though we do not yet know what path market actors will choose, evolution away from board governance seems sensible and likely and the path for that evolution should be cleared of legal and regulatory obstacles.


* Loula Fuller and Dan Myers Professor of Law, Florida State University College of Law.  For helpful comments and conversations about this project, I thank Anthony Casey, Larry Cunningham, Jill Fisch, Brian Galle, Andrew Gold, Andrew Hessick, Carissa Hessick, Claire Hill, Zachary Kramer, Dan Markel, Larry Ribstein and participants at workshops at the 2010 Law and Society Association Annual Meeting, the Florida State University College of Law, and the University of Florida Levin College of Law.  I am very grateful to Lauren Vickroy and Sharee Davis for excellent research assistance.

[1]. Korn/Ferry Int’l, 33rd Annual Board of Directors Study 23 (2006).

[2]. See Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, §141(e) (2010).

[3]. Ronald J. Gilson & Reinier Kraakman, Reinventing the Outside Director: An Agenda for Institutional Investors, 43 Stan. L. Rev. 863, 872 (1991).

[4]. Douglas G. Baird & Robert K. Rasmussen, Private Debt and the Missing Lever of Corporate Governance, 154 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1209, 1226–28 (2006) [hereinafter Baird & Rasmussen, Private Debt].

[5]. Lucian Ayre Bebchuk, Jesse M. Fried & David I. Walker, Managerial Power and Rent Extraction in the Design of Executive Compensation, 69 U. Chi. L. Rev. 751 (2002).

[6]. Abigail Evans, Cooperation or Co-Optation: When Does a Union Become Employer-Dominated Under Section 8(A)(2) of the National Labor Relations Act?, 100 Colum. L. Rev. 1022, 1048–49 (2000).

[7]. Throughout this Article, when I refer to “public corporations,” I mean public firms with widely dispersed share ownership.  There are many public firms dominated by single shareholders or small groups of shareholders, but this Article’s proposal is aimed at those with widely held ownership.

[8]. Jonathan R. Macey, Corporate Governance: Promises Kept, Promises Broken 56 (2008).

[9]. See Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 141(e) (2010); Macey, supra note 8 at 51–52.

[10]. Macey, supra note 8, at 56 (“A crucial, but wholly unexamined, assumption underlying this foundational theory of corporate governance is that boards of directors can reasonably be expected to do what is required of them.  This assumption cannot withstand scrutiny.”).

[11]. See, e.g., Margaret M. Blair & Lynn A. Stout, A Team Production Theory of Corporate Law, 85 Va. L. Rev. 247 (1999); Lisa M. Fairfax, The Uneasy Case for the Inside Director, 96 Iowa L. Rev. 127 (2010); Jill E. Fisch, Taking Boards Seriously, 19 Cardozo L. Rev. 265 (1997) (warning that reforms calling for uniform standards for boards of directors may not improve corporate governance); Gilson & Kraakman, supra note 3; Donald C. Langevoort, The Human Nature of Corporate Boards: Law, Norms, and the Unintended Consequences of Independence and Accountability, 89 Geo. L.J. 797 (2001).

[12]. See, e.g., Sanjai Bhagat & Bernard Black, The Uncertain Relationship Between Board Composition and Firm Performance, 54 Bus. Law. 921 (1999); Victor Brudney, The Independent Director—Heavenly City or Potemkin Village?, 95 Harv. L. Rev. 597, (1982); Laura Lin, The Effectiveness of Outside Directors as a Corporate Governance Mechanism: Theories and Evidence, 90 Nw. U. L. Rev. 898 (1996).

[13]. Compare, for example, the perspective of Professor Stephen Bainbridge with those of his critics.  Bainbridge strongly supports boards, arguing consistently that a board of directors exercising unfettered discretion should serve at the top of the corporate decision-making structure.  See, e.g., Stephen M. Bainbridge, Director Primacy and Shareholder Disempowerment, 119 Harv. L. Rev. 1735 (2006); Stephen M. Bainbridge, Director Primacy: The Means and Ends of Corporate Governance, 97 Nw. U. L. Rev. 547 (2003) [hereinafter Bainbridge, Director Primacy]; Stephen M. Bainbridge, Why A Board? Group Decisionmaking in Corporate Governance, 55 Vand. L. Rev. 1 (2002) [hereinafter Bainbridge, Why a Board?] (explaining why a group, rather than an individual CEO, should dominate the corporate governance structure).  By contrast, other distinguished corporate law scholars challenge these views, emphasizing improvements in shareholder power, among other options.  See, e.g., Macey, supra note 7; Gilson & Kraakman, supra note 3; Lucian Arye Bebchuk, The Case for Increasing Shareholder Power, 118 Harv. L. Rev. 833 (2005).

[14]. An equity trustee is selected by a committee of the corporation’s seven largest shareholders and represents the entire common shareholder class to management in performing the shareholder role in corporate governance.  For further explanation and discussion of the concept of an “equity trustee,” see Kelli A. Alces, The Equity Trustee, 42 Ariz. St. L.J. 717 (2010) [hereinafter Alces, Equity Trustee] (developing in detail the innovation of the equity trustee and explaining what it is, how it could be implemented, and what its role in corporate governance would be); Kelli A. Alces, Debunking the Corporate Fiduciary Myth, 35 J. Corp. L. 239 (2009) [hereinafter Alces, Debunking] (arguing that corporate officers and directors do not truly stand in fiduciary relation to shareholders and the firm, and that equity representation could facilitate meaningful contracting to develop and enforce more effective corporate governance relationships); Kelli A. Alces, Strategic Governance, 50 Ariz. L. Rev. 1053 (2008) [hereinafter Alces, Strategic Governance] (suggesting that an equity trustee could help balance against strong creditor power over corporate management in times of financial distress to provide continuity in equity representation during times of differing financial success).

[15]. Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 141(a) (2010).

[16]. See, e.g., Bainbridge, Why a Board?, supra note 13, at 53.

[17]. Franklin A. Gevurtz, The Historical and Political Origins of the Corporate Board of Directors, 33 Hofstra L. Rev. 89, 108 (2004).

[18]. Id. at 110.

[19]. Id.

[20]. Franklin A. Gevurtz, The Function of “Dysfunctional” Boards, 77 U. Cin. L. Rev. 391, 395 (2008).

[21]. See Elizabeth Cosenza, The Holy Grail of Corporate Governance Reform: Independence or Democracy?, 2007 BYU L. Rev. 1, 18 (“Whereas in the 1960s most boards had a majority of in-house, non-independent directors, most boards today have a majority of outside, independent directors.”); Tamar Frankel, Corporate Boards of Directors: Advisors or Supervisors?, 77 U. Cin. L. Rev. 501, 504 (2008).

[22]. Cosenza, supra note 21, at 18 –19.

[23]. Frankel, supra note 21, at 505 (stating that, over time, CEOs began choosing the board members, rather than the board choosing CEOs, and the board’s role became advisory, rather than supervisory).  See also, Jay W. Lorsch & Elizabeth MacIver, Pawns or Potentates: The Reality of America’s Corporate Board 20 (1989) [hereinafter Pawns or Potentates] (explaining that traditionally, nominating and selecting board members was the “exclusive responsibility of the CEO”).

[24]. Frankel, supra note 21, at 505.

[25]. Id. at 504–06.

[26]. Melvin Aron Eisenberg, Corporations and Other Business Organizations 204 (8th ed. 2000); Frankel, supra note 21, at 503–04.

[27]. Frankel, supra note 21, at 508.

[28]. Id. at 507 (quoting Edward S. Herman, The Limits of the Market as a Discipline in Corporate Governance, 9 Del. J. Corp. L. 530, 533 (1984)).

[29]. Fisch, supra note 10, at 269.

[30]. Frankel, supra note 21, at 506–07.  For the SEC’s definition of independent director, see 15 U.S.C. § 80a-2(a)(19) (2006). See also, Developments in the Law—Corporations and Society, 117 Harv. L. Rev. 2181, 2187–94 (2004) (explaining both the NYSE and NASDAQ definitions of independent director).

[31]. Fisch, supra note 11, at 271.

[32]. Id. at 268–72.

[33]. Mark S. Beasley, An Empirical Analysis of the Relation between the Board of Director Composition and Financial Statement Fraud, 71 Acct. Rev. 443, 460 (1996) (finding that firms with larger proportions of outside directors were less likely to commit financial statement fraud).

[34]. Fisch, supra note 11, at 270–71.

[35]. Id.

[36]. Frankel, supra note 21, at 506–07.

[37]. This focus on directors may explain why Congress addressed officer accountability directly in the Sarbanes-Oxley Act of 2002. Pub. L No. 107–204, 116 Stat. 745.  Sarbanes-Oxley (“SOX”) was the congressional response to the corporate scandals of the early 2000s.  A jurisdictional glitch in Delaware law that made it impossible to get personal jurisdiction over corporate officers sitting in other states has been corrected, so we may begin to see more suits against officers for breach of fiduciary duty.  Of course, liability for poor decision making is exceptionally rare for directors, as they receive generous protection from the business judgment rule and Delaware General Corporation Law section 102(b)(7).

[38]. For a general discussion of board independence, see Stephen M. Bainbridge, Corporate Law 80–84 (2d ed. 2009).

[39]. 15 U.S.C. §§ 78j-1, 78j-3 (2010); Fairfax, supra note 11, at 136.

[40]. Lawrence A. Cunningham, Rediscovering Board Expertise: Legal Implications of the Empirical Literature, 77 U. Cin. L. Rev. 465, 478 (2008).

[41]. NASDAQ Rules 5600–5640: Corporate Governance Requirements, available at http://nasdaq.cchwallstreet.com/NASDAQTools/bookmark.asp?id
=nasdaq-rule_5600&manual=/nasdaq/main/nasdaq-equityrules/ (last visited Sept. 16, 2011) (outlining qualitative rules relating to boards of directors, including audit committees, independent oversight of executive compensation, director nomination, related party transactions, and shareholder voting rights); NYSE Amex PART 8 Corporate Governance Requirements (2010), available at http://wallstreet.cch.com/AMEXTools/bookmark.asp?id=sx-policymanual-amex
-acg_8&manual=/AMEX/CompanyGuide/amex-company-guide/ (last visited Sept. 16, 2011) (specifying corporate governance listing requirements).

[42]. Daniele Marchesani, The Concept of Autonomy and the Independent Director of Public Corporations, 2 Berkeley Bus. L.J. 315, 322 (2005) (observing that Delaware corporate law permits transactions where a director has a personal financial interest, so long as a majority of independent directors—those without a personal interest at stake—approve the transaction).

[43]. Gilson & Kraakman, supra note 3, at 873.

[44]. Brudney, supra note 12, at 613 (“No definition of independence yet offered precludes an independent director from being a social friend of, or a member of the same clubs, associations, or charitable efforts as, the persons whose compensation or self-dealing transaction he is asked to assess.”).

[45]. Fairfax, supra note 11, at 146–49; Gilson & Kraakman, supra note 3, at 875 (observing that no definition of independence prohibits outside directors from befriending officers, and outside directors are often the officers of other companies and therefore will not monitor any more vigorously than they believe they themselves should be monitored).  For an in-depth discussion of the social dynamics of corporate boards, see generally Rakesh Khurana & Katharina Pick, The Social Nature of Boards, 70 Brook. L. Rev. 1259 (2005).

[46]. Gilson & Kraakman, supra note 3, at 875 (describing the various institutional, social, and financial mechanisms that draw outside directors towards officers, rather than shareholders).

[47]. Id. (noting that “[sixty-three] percent of outside directors of public companies are chief executive officers of other public companies”); see, e.g., Pawns or Potentates, supra note 23, at 18–19 (discussing the benefits and detriments of board members holding multiple positions as CEO in other public corporations).

[48]. Gilson & Kraakman, supra note 3, at 875 (arguing that “in addition to these dependency, ideological, and social obstacles to monitoring, outside directors typically lack an affirmative incentive to monitor effectively”).

[49]. Id.

[50]. Rachel A. Fink, Social Ties in the Boardroom: Changing the Definition of Director Independence to Eliminate “Rubber-Stamping” Boards, 79 S. Cal. L. Rev. 455, 464 (2006).

[51]. The American Bar Association has made this observation.  Report of the American Bar Association Task Force on Corporate Responsibility, 59 Bus. Law. 145, 158 (2003) (“Outside directors too often have relied almost exclusively upon senior executive officers, and advisers selected by such officers, for information and guidance about corporate affairs.”).

[52]. As Jonathan Macey points out:

[M]anagers have extremely high-powered incentives to present themselves, and their work, to directors in the most favorable light possible.  This, in turn, strongly suggests that the flow of information from management to the board will be biased in ways that put management in the most favorable light possible and undermine the effectiveness of dissident or uncooperative directors.

Macey, supra note 8, at 60.

[53]. See generally Lisa Fairfax, Government Governance and the Need to Reconcile Government Regulation with Board Fiduciary Duties, 95 Minn. L. Rev. 1692 (2011).

[54]. Id.; see also In re Am. Int’l Group, Inc. Consol. Derivative Litig., 965 A.2d 763 (Del. Ch. 2009); In re Citigroup Inc. S’holder Derivative Litig., 964 A.2d 106 (Del. Ch. 2009).

[55]. SOX is a prime example of this.  Pub. L. No. 111–203, § 10C, 124 Stat. 1900, 1900–04 (2002) (codified as amended at 15 U.S.C. § 78j-3 (2010)).  SOX requires board committees that focus on director selection, compensation, and auditing to be composed of independent directors.  Public listing standards promulgated at the same time require public firms to have majority independent boards.  The Dodd-Frank Act also requires some level of independence for various boards of directors.  Pub. L. No. 111–203, § 932(t), 124 Stat. 1872, 1882–83 (2010).  See id. at § 10C (outlining various requirements for the compensation committees for the board of directors of an issuer); see also id. at § 932(t)(2) (requiring one half of a nationally recognized statistical rating organization’s board of directors to be composed of independent members).

[56]. Gilson & Kraakman, supra note 3, at 884–86.

[57]. Id. at 885–86.

[58]. Id. at 885.

[59]. See Mark J. Roe, A Political Theory of American Corporate Finance, 91 Colum. L. Rev. 10, 56 (1991).

[60]. See Bainbridge, Why a Board?, supra note 13, at 7 (explaining that creating a hierarchical monitoring scheme in M-form corporations “addresses the problems of uncertainty, bounded rationality, and shirking faced by monitors . . .”).

[61]. Roe, supra note 59, at 56.

[62]. Id.

[63]. Id.

[64]. Bainbridge, Why a Board?, supra note 13, at 7 (explaining that the board of directors is at the top of the hierarchical organization of the corporation).

[65]. Id. at 4 (describing “authority-based decision making”).

[66]. See id. at 5.

[67]. See id. at 45.

[68]. Id. at 45–47.

[69]. See Gilson & Kraakman, supra note 3, at 875.

[70]. Edward B. Rock & Michael L. Wachter, Symposium: Norms and Corporate Law: Introduction, 149 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1607, 1609 (2001).

[71]. See, e.g., Stone v. Ritter, 911 A.2d 362, 364–65 (Del. 2006) (dismissing shareholders’ complaint because there was no proof that the board knew of the inadequacy of the corporation’s internal controls); In re Caremark Int’l, 698 A.2d 959, 970–72 (Del. Ch. 1996).

[72]. In re Citigroup Inc. S’holder Derivative Litig., 964 A.2d 106, 129–32 (Del. Ch. 2009) (holding that while Citigroup officers and board members may not have adequately understood the riskiness of the investments that constituted a large part of the company’s profit, and caused the company’s eventual collapse, their actions were covered by the business judgment rule).

[73]. Roe, supra note 59, at 14 (stating that scattered shareholders do not intervene in the decision making of management until something dramatic, such as a hostile takeover or leveraged buyout, occurs).

[74]. Macey, supra note 8, at 62 (“Where a CEO makes a proposal to a group of board members, the first board member to raise questions or to disagree with management bears the greatest risk of being branded uncooperative or non-collegial.”).

[75]. But see id. at 54 (stating that the role of directors has recently expanded to include greater participation in management decision making, in addition to its monitoring function).

[76]. Roe, supra note 59 (describing probabilistic monitoring).

[77]. Bainbridge, Why a Board?, supra note 13, at 49–54 (discussing the formal structure of the corporate governance system); Lynn A. Stout, The Shareholder as Ulysses: Some Empirical Evidence on Why Investors in Public Corporations Tolerate Board Governance, 152 U. Pa. L. Rev. 667, 668 (2003) (stating that directors decide “how the firm shall be run, whom it shall hire, . . . in what it shall invest [and] . . . whether corporate earnings will be used to pay dividends—or used instead to build empires, raise salaries, and support charities”).

[78]. See Frankel, supra note 21, at 504–07.

[79]. Donald C. Langevoort, Commentary: Puzzles About Corporate Boards and Board Diversity, 89 N.C. L. Rev. 841, 843 (2011) [hereinafter Langevoort, Commentary].

[80]. Id. (“[S]urvey data indicate that this is the function board members think they are performing most of the time.”) (citing Renee Adams et al., The Role of Boards of Directors in Corporate Governance: A Conceptual Framework & Survey, 48 J. Econ. Lit. 58, 64–66 (2010)).

[81]. Bhagat & Black, supra note 12, at 921.

[82]. Nicholas Johnson, Open Meeting and Closed Minds: Another Road to the Mountaintop, 53 Drake L. Rev. 11, 42 (2004).

[83]. See Robert W. Hamilton, Corporate Governance in America 1950–2000: Major Changes But Uncertain Benefits, 25 J. Corp. L. 349, 351 (2000).

[84]. Johnson, supra note 82.

[85]. Lynne L. Dallas, The Relational Board: Three Theories of Corporate Boards of Directors, 22 J. Corp. L. 1, 5 (1996) (discussing managerial dominance of the board).

[86]. Gilson & Kraakman, supra note 3, at 889.

[87]. Id.

[88]. Delaware courts often defer to the judgment of independent directors when those directors, or a special litigation made up of independent directors, refuse to bring a suit demanded by shareholders or move to have a derivative suit dismissed.  See Cunningham, supra note 40, at 469.

[89]. Cunningham notes the progression of this deference to the judgment of independent directors in the takeover context by tracking the jurisprudence during the takeover boom of the 1980s.

Delaware courts, continuing a pattern dating at least to the bribery scandal litigation, strengthened the appeal of independent directors by increasingly deferring to their decisions.  Using independent directors insulated from judicial review, self-interested transactions, cash-out mergers, adoption of poison pills, resisting hostile takeover threats, and simply “saying no” to them.

Id. at 470.

[90]. Unocal Corp. v. Mesa Petroleum Co., 493 A.2d 946, 954 (Del. 1985).

[91]. Id.

[92]. Id. at 955.

[93]. Id.  Even so, boards are allowed wide discretion to block takeover attempts, and corporate law has evolved to allow executives to make hostile takeovers virtually impossible.  Macey, supra note 8, at 123.  Because insiders are so thoroughly protected by antitakeover laws and a judiciary that is traditionally sympathetic to their interests in the takeover context, the threat of a takeover or a merger offer does not threaten their position in the firm as much as it otherwise might.

[94]. Curiously, a board’s decision to choose a course that is designed to enhance long-term shareholder or corporate value over short-term value was upheld in the takeover context.  The Delaware Supreme Court’s decision in Paramount Commc’ns, Inc. v. Time, Inc., 571 A.2d 1140 (Del. 1989), is the oft-cited example of a court allowing the board to make such a judgment over the objection of shareholders who would have preferred to take a higher cash value for their shares in a tender offer.  See also Stout, supra note 77, at 696 (“Change of control transactions consequently provide some of the best illustrations of the remarkable degree of discretion corporate law grants directors to favor nonshareholder interests at the shareholders’ expense.”).

[95]. Langevoort, Commentary, supra note 79, at 847.

[96]. See Blair & Stout, supra note 11, at 280–81; Stout, supra note 77, at 686–88.

[97]. Stephen M. Bainbridge, The Board of Directors as Nexus of Contracts, 88 Iowa L. Rev. 1, 9–10 (2002) (describing the “nexus of contracts” theory as the dominant model of the corporation among legal scholars, and placing its origins in Ronald Coase’s article, The Nature of the Firm, 4 Economica (n.s.) 386 (1937)); Antony Page, Has Corporate Law Failed? Addressing Proposals for Reform, 107 Mich. L. Rev. 979, 984 (2009) (explaining that in the “nexus of contracts” theory, the state supplies a standard contract in the form of default rules, which parties may negotiate to modify).  Note that there is some dispute about this characterization of the firm, with some scholars arguing that the modern corporation is a heavily regulated, formalized structure that lacks the flexibility in form that a “nexus of contracts” would contemplate.  See generally, Larry E. Ribstein, The Rise of the Uncorporation (2010).  Still others argue that the firm cannot really be a “nexus of contracts” because shareholders are unable to actually negotiate contract terms with the firm or its management.  See, e.g., Victor Brudney, Corporate Governance, Agency Costs, and the Rhetoric of Contract, 85 Colum. L. Rev. 1403, 1415–16 (1985) (“[T]o impute to investors knowledge of either the terms of the law when they first enter the ‘contract’ or the changes in the law while stock is held is pure fiction in the case of most individual investors.  In the case of institutional investors or market professionals who advise individuals about investments, it is hardly less.”).  See generally Robert C. Clark, Agency Costs Versus Fiduciary Duties, in Principals and Agents: The Structure of Business 55 (John W. Pratt & Richard Zeckhauser eds., 1985).

[98]. See, e.g., Anne Tucket Nees, Who’s the Boss? Unmasking Oversight Liability Within the Corporate Puzzle, 35 Del. J. Corp. L. 199, 251 (2010).

[99]. While “[s]hareholders nominally have the right to elect directors . . . , the dispersion of shares . . . [makes] the board . . . effectively self-perpetuating.”  Baird & Rasmussen, Private Debt, supra note 4, at 1214; see also Douglas G. Baird & Robert K. Rasmussen, The End of Bankruptcy, 55 Stan. L. Rev. 751, 779 (2002) [hereinafter Baird & Rasmussen, Bankruptcy] (“The board can be replaced by the shareholders.”).  By contrast, creditors influence board and officer decision making in a more substantive way, particularly during times of financial distress.  See Baird & Rasmussen, Private Debt, supra note 4, at 1242–45.  For example, unlike shareholders, creditors—through elaborate loan covenants—have the ability to replace the CEO of the distressed borrower-corporation.  Id. at 1211.  Also, shareholders, because of their wide dispersal, “cannot often galvanize quickly when misfortune strikes.”  Id. at 1242.  Thus, not only do creditors exert more power, they actually provide a more efficient method of oversight.  Id.  Finally, labor unions similarly exert substantial influence over decision making through their stockholdings as pension funds.  See, e.g., Stewart J. Schwab & Randall S. Thomas, Realigning Corporate Governance: Shareholder Activism by Labor Unions, 96 Mich. L. Rev. 1018 (1998).  One way unions have exerted influence is through the heavy use of Rule 14a-8 to place proposals on the company’s ballot.  Id. at 1045.  Such union-sponsored proposals usually “involve standard corporate-governance issues designed to maximize the value of the corporation by improving the efficiency of the market for corporate control and aligning manager incentives with shareholder interests.”  Id.

[100]. For example, Visteon Corporation entered into a loan agreement with five banks following a negotiated bailout with Ford Motor Company.  The agreement contained various affirmative and negative covenants, including granting the bank group priority on after-acquired property and a prohibition on certain debt ratios.  See Visteon Corp., Amended and Restated Five-Year Revolving Loan Credit Agreement (Form 8-K) exhibit 10.4, §§ 7.9(a), 7A.1 (June 30, 2005).  For additional examples, see Delphi Corp., $2,825,000,000 Five-Year Third Amended and Restated Credit Agreement (Form 8-K) (June 15, 2005); Gen. Motors Corp., 364-Day Revolving Credit Agreement (Form 10-Q) (Aug. 7, 2007).

[101]. See Visteon Corp., Amended and Restated Five-Year Revolving Loan Credit Agreement (Form 8-K) exhibit 10.4, § 8, (June 30, 2005).

[102]. Heinrich Harries, Co-Financing Between Public and Private Institutions for Development Financing, 32 Am. U. L. Rev. 111, 117 n.15 (1982) (“A cross-default clause in a loan agreement that a default on any one loan by the borrower entitles the lender(s) to declare the borrower in default of its other loan obligations.”); see also Laura Lin, Shift of Fiduciary Duty Upon Corporate Insolvency: Proper Scope of Director’s Duty to Creditors, 46 Vand. L. Rev. 1485, 1507 (1993).

[103]. One way creditors may have leverage over management is through debt contracts which give the creditors the power to place handpicked persons on the board of directors in times of financial distress.  Baird & Rasmussen, Bankruptcy, supra note 99, at 779.

[104]. Baird & Rasmussen, Private Debt, supra note 4, at 1233.

[105]. Shareholders may also allege a breach of fiduciary duty to the extent the board seems to prefer creditors’ interests or preferred courses of action to their own but are likely to find that the business judgment rule precludes relief.  See Credit Lyonnais Bank Nederland, N.V. v. Pathe Commc’ns Corp., No. 12150, 1991 WL 277613, at *36 n.22 (Del. Ch. 1991).

[106]. Labor unions can be powerful influences on officers and directors and may have interests adverse to those of shareholders and lenders.  The struggle between General Motors and the United Auto Workers for years while GM crept slowly toward insolvency illustrates the point.  See Steven Greenhouse, G.M.’s New Owners, U.S. and Labor, Adjust to Roles, N.Y. Times, June 1, 2009, http://www.nytimes.com/2009/06/02/business/02uaw.html (discussing the UAW’s use of the threat of a strike to extract concessions from GM management, a move which ultimately contributed heavily to GM’s bankruptcy).

[107]. Credit Lyonnais Bank, 1991 WL 277613, at *36 n.22.

[108]. See Fisch, supra note 11, at 274 (explaining that the board must have detailed knowledge of the corporation prior to making decisions over corporate matters).

[109]. See Benjamin E. Hermalin & Michael S. Weisbach, Endogenously Chosen Boards of Directors and Their Monitoring of the CEO, 88 Am. Econ. Rev. 96 (1998) (putting forth a model that demonstrates that boards become less independent and thus engage in less monitoring of a CEO the longer the CEO has been in office); Langevoort, Commentary, supra note 79, at 846–47.

[110]. Langevoort, supra note 11, at 802–03.

[111]. Lynne Dallas, The Multiple Roles of Corporate Boards of Directors, 40 San Diego L. Rev. 781, 805 (2003); Langevoort, Commentary, supra note 79, at 843.  Professor Dallas explains that the relational role of outside directors allows the corporation to: “(1) coordinate with its external environment, (2) obtain advice and access to information from directors with differing backgrounds, skills, and networks, (3) enhance the support, status, and legitimacy of the corporation in the eyes of relevant audiences, and (4) effectuate monitoring of the strategic direction of the corporation.”  Dallas, supra.

[112]. Langevoort, Commentary, supra note 79, at 843 (noting that the advisory function could be performed by consultants while acknowledging that directors with important political or government connections can be valuable to some firms).

[113]. See Lin, supra note 12, at 914–16 (discussing ways the board of directors’ ability to monitor management is restricted by managements’ control of information and expertise).

[114]. The Coase Theorem, developed by Ronald Coase in his famous article The Problem of Social Cost, 3 J.L. & Econ. 1 (1960), dictates that if transaction costs are zero, then parties will reach an efficient distribution of wealth between them, regardless of their relative bargaining power or strength.

[115]. Benjamin E. Hermalin & Michael S. Weisbach, Boards of Directors as an Endogenously Determined Institution: A Survey of the Economic Literature, Fed. Res. Bank N.Y. Econ. Pol’y Rev., Apr. 2003, at 7, 7.

[116]. Adolf Berle and Gardiner Means are widely credited with describing the separation of ownership from control that defines the modern public corporation in their book The Modern Corporation and Private Property, first published almost eighty years ago.  Adolf A. Berle & Gardiner M. Means, The Modern Corporation & Private Property (Transaction Publishers 2009) (1932).  Since the publication of The Modern Corporation & Private Property, corporate governance law and scholarship has focused primarily on reducing the agency costs Berle and Means illuminated.  In another seminal work, Jensen and Meckling explained how various capital structures could work to constrain agency costs within the firm.  See generally Michael C. Jensen & William H. Meckling, Theory of the Firm: Managerial Behavior, Agency Costs and Ownership Structure, 3 J. Fin. Econ. 305 (1976).

[117]. See Bhagat & Black, supra note 12.

[118]. See Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 141(a) (2010) (“The business and affairs of every corporation organized under this chapter shall be managed by or under the direction of a board of directors . . . .”).

[119]. See Langevoort, supra note 11, at 814 (“[T]he ideal board structure may be firm-specific . . . .”); Roberta Romano, The Sarbanes-Oxley Act and the Making of Quack Corporate Governance, 114 Yale L.J. 1521, 1529 (2005).

[120]. See supra Part I.B.

[121]. See Alces, Debunking, supra note 14, at 249 (explaining that managers will permit their own self interests to direct their business decisions, resulting in greater monitoring of the corporation than any other form of loyalty or fiduciary duty would produce).

[122]. See Alces, Strategic Governance, supra note 14, at 1053–54.

[123]. This investor board structure is similar to corporate governance in other countries.  In Japan, for instance, corporations are owned and dominated by large banks.  German corporations have two boards—one that supervises and one that manages.  The supervisory board is selected by shareholders and labor unions and monitors the management board.  German banks dominate corporate shareholding, as in Japan, and shares in both countries are held in large blocks. Franklin Allen & Mengxin Zhao, The Corporate Governance Model of Japan: Shareholders are Not Rulers, 36 PKU Bus. Rev. 98 (2007), translated in Beijing Bus. Rev. (May 13, 2007) (working paper), available at http://finance.wharton.upenn.edu/~allenf/download/Vita/Japan‑Corporate‑Governance.pdf.  See generally Thomas J. Andre, Jr., Some Reflections on German Corporate Governance: A Glimpse at German Supervisory Boards, 70 Tul. L. Rev. 1819 (1996).  These economies are different from ours, however, and the dominance of banks on both the lending and shareholding side is very different from the American system.  The American system is intentionally diffuse relative to the other systems and no one bank is as able to completely dominate an American corporation.  Roe, supra note 54.  Therefore, the investor board and post-board firm suggested here is very different from the practical realities of foreign systems.

[124]. Alces, Strategic Governance, supra note 14, at 1073–78; Baird & Rasmussen, Private Debt, supra note 4, at 1231–32.

[125]. Julian Velasco, The Fundamental Rights of the Shareholder, 40 U.C. Davis L. Rev. 407, 409 (2006) (arguing that shareholders’ rights to elect directors and to sell their shares are more important than other shareholder rights).

[126]. Alces, Equity Trustee, supra note 14, at 747–50.

[127]. In fact, the power of the lender to appoint new management may be an event of default under a loan covenant or a condition of a loan itself.  See Baird & Rasmussen, Private Debt, supra note 4, at 1233; Frederick Tung, Leverage in the Board Room: The Unsung Influence of Private Lenders in Corporate Governance, 57 UCLA L. Rev. 115, 156–58 (2009).

[128]. Baird & Rasmussen, Private Debt, supra note 4, at 1233; see Tung, supra note 115, at 156–58.

[129]. See Tung, supra note 127, at 119, 133.

[130]. See id. at 118.

[131]. See Fairfax, supra note 11, at 130 (explaining that there is an “overwhelming consensus that boards should be dominated by ‘independent’ directors . . . [because they are] better equipped to monitor the corporation, detect fraud, and protect shareholders’ interests”).

[132]. See Macey, supra note 8, at 54.

[133]. See Jennifer S. Taub, Able But Not Willing: The Failure of Mutual Fund Advisors to Advocate for Shareholders’ Rights, 34 J. Corp. L. 843, 849–51 (2009).

[134]. John C. Coffee, Jr., Gatekeeper Failure and Reform: The Challenge of Fashioning Relevant Reforms, 84 B.U. L. Rev. 301, 326 (2004).

[135]. The equity committee structure would make shareholders a more attentive group in monitoring the equity trustee than current beneficial owners are in monitoring the institutions managing their investments.  While the structure adds a layer of agents to agents watching agents watching agents, the focus of shareholder power in fewer, more sophisticated hands makes shareholder activity easier to observe and thus more accountable to the larger class of shareholders.  Alces, Equity Trustee, supra note 14, at 748–50.

[136]. See id. at 720.

[137]. Id. at 739.

[138]. Mark J. Loewenstein, The Quiet Transformation of Corporate Law, 57 SMU L. Rev. 353, 376 (2004) (“American corporate governance is wedded to the notion of directors who serve only part time and who have substantial, often overwhelming, responsibilities outside of the corporation(s) on whose board(s) they serve.”).  Twelve of Enron’s fourteen board members were outside directors with other demanding jobs.  The Chairman of the Audit Committee, for example, also worked at Stanford’s School of Business.  See Lisa M. Fairfax, The Sarbanes-Oxley Act as Confirmation of Recent Trends in Director and Officer Fiduciary Obligations, 76 St. John’s L. Rev. 953, 957 n.20 (2002).

[139]. Gilson & Kraakman, supra note 3, at 884–92.

[140]. Douglas G. Baird & M. Todd Henderson, Other People’s Money, 60 Stan. L. Rev. 1309, 1339 (2008).

[141]. Id. at 1315–56.

[142]. Id. at 1342–43.

[143]. See id.

[144]. See Alces, Strategic Governance, supra note 14, at 1098 (“[T]he equity trustee would monitor the corporation and remain informed as to its financial condition and important business decisions and capital structure, ready to spring into action when its agreement with the corporation requires it.”).

[145]. Langevoort, supra note 11, at 813–14.

[146]. Alces, Strategic Governance, supra note 13, at 1061–63.

[147]. See infra Part II.D.

[148]. Baird & Henderson, supra note 140, at 1338–41.

[149]. Id.

[150]. Id.

[151]. Id.

[152]. Lawrence A. Cunningham, Commonalities and Prescriptions in the Vertical Dimension of Global Corporate Governance, 84 Cornell L. Rev. 1133, 1165–66 (1999) (explaining that fiduciary rhetoric performs socializing, educational, and proselytizing functions in corporate governance).

[153]. Alces, Debunking, supra note 14, at 256 (“The current system relies on a clumsy combination of smoke and mirrors to discourage bad behavior through stern threats of possible liability while only punishing truly egregious behavior, often ineffectively and after it is too late.”).

[154]. Id. at 243 (stating that “fiduciary duties are not relied upon to discipline managers, and they are not enforced very often”).  The Delaware Legislature has similarly reflected this desire to punish directors without imposing personal liability.  Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 102(b)(7) (2008).  See Alces, Debunking, supra note 14, at 251 (“[T]he Delaware corporation statute allows directors . . . to opt out of personal liability for breaches of the duty of care.  [Therefore,] [o]fficers and directors must be punished for incompetence in other ways.”).

[155]. Baird & Henderson, supra note 140, at 1309–10.

[156]. Some scholars question whether the same duty of loyalty applies to officers as applies to directors.  Lyman P.Q. Johnson & David Millon, Recalling Why Corporate Officers are Fiduciaries, 46 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 1597, 1600–08 (2005) (arguing that because officers are appointed, rather than elected, officers should be held to stricter fiduciary standards than directors, with agency law serving as the basis for imposing liability).  Still, a contractual system that does not rely on fiduciary duties would mean that officers would not be held to a fiduciary standard.

[157]. Edward B. Rock & Michael L. Wachter, Islands of Conscious Power: Law, Norms, and the Self-Governing Corporation, 149 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1619, 1640–45 (2001).

[158]. Geoffrey P. Miller, A Modest Proposal for Fixing Delaware’s Broken Duty of Care, 2010 Colum. Bus. L. Rev. 319, 332–33 (2010) (“Fear of overwhelming judgments against directors for a good decision gone wrong might deter people from serving on boards, or might discourage them from undertaking risky but desirable ventures if they do serve.”).

[159]. David Rosenberg, Supplying the Adverb: The Future of Corporate Risk-Taking and the Business Judgment Rule, 6 Berkeley Bus. L.J. 216, 221 (2009) (discussing arguments in favor of risk taking and the importance of allowing managers to exercise their business judgment in taking risks).

[160]. Miller, supra note 158.

[161]. Breach of the duty to act in good faith can also lead to liability, but the meaning of that term has been debated.  Most recently, bad faith has been characterized as malicious, willful behavior or behavior that evinces a complete disregard for the director or officer’s duties to the corporation.  See Andrew S. Gold, The New Concept of Loyalty in Corporate Law, 43 U.C. Davis L. Rev. 457, 469 (2009) (describing the Delaware Supreme Court’s decision in Disney V as defining a violation of good faith as acting with “an intent to do harm,” or actions “reflect[ing] a conscious disregard of a director’s duties”).  For unincorporated entities, Gold describes good faith as “contractual gap-fillers: they are a means of filling in implied terms when contracts are silent as to specific contingencies.”  Andrew S. Gold, On the Elimination of Fiduciary Duties: A Theory of Good Faith for Unincorporated Firms, 41 Wake Forest L. Rev. 123, 127 (2006).

[162]. The Delaware Code was amended in 2006 to specifically allow for this type of removal process.  See William K. Sjostrom, Jr. & Young Sang Kim, Majority Voting for the Election of Directors, 40 Conn. L. Rev. 459, 474–75 (2007).

[163]. Macey, supra note 8, at 58–60.

[164]. Baird & Rasmussen, Private Debt, supra note 4, at 1242–45.

[165]. A. Mechele Dickerson, Privatizing Ethics in Corporate Reorganizations, 93 Minn. L. Rev. 875, 915 (2009) (stating that “[e]mpirical studies have found that officers are replaced in roughly half of the firms who are in financial distress”); Tung, supra note 127, at 157 (explaining that the likelihood of CEO turnover is especially related to financial difficulties for firms with private debt).

[166]. David V. Maurer, Golden Parachutes—Executive Compensation or Executive Overreaching?, 9 J. Corp. L. 346, 351–52 (1984); Mary Siegel, Tender Offer Defensive Tactics: A Proposal for Reform, 36 Hastings L.J. 377, 377 n.4 (1985) (explaining that the justification for golden parachutes is that management, knowing it will be financially secure regardless of who is the victor in a takeover battle, will be able to accept or reject the tender offer in an objective fashion); Randall S. Thomas & Harwell Wells, Executive Compensation in the Courts: Board Capture, Optimal Contracting, and Officers’ Fiduciary Duties, 95 Minn. L. Rev. 846, 854 (2011).

[167]. Bainbridge, Shareholder Disempowerment, supra note 13, at 1747.

[168]. Id.

[169]. Id.

[170]. See, e.g., Bainbridge, Director Primacy, supra note 13; Baird & Rasmussen, Private Debt, supra note 4; Bebchuk, supra note 13; Dallas, supra note 82; Einer Elhauge, Sacrificing Corporate Profits in the Public Interest, 80 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 733 (2005); Frederick Tung, The New Death of Contract: Creeping Corporate Fiduciary Duties for Creditors, 57 Emory L.J. 809 (2008).

[171]. See Bainbridge, Director Primacy, supra note 13 (arguing that balancing the various interests of corporate constituents is a matter that should be left to the discretion of the board of directors); Blair & Stout, supra note 11 (explaining the mediating function of a board of directors).

[172]. Bainbridge, Why a Board?, supra note 13, at 9; James P. Holdcroft, Jr. & Jonathan R. Macey, Flexibility in Determining the Role of the Board of Directors in the Age of Information, 19 Cardozo L. Rev. 291, 291–92 (1997).

[173]. Tung, supra note 127, at 125.

[174]. Baird & Rasmussen, Bankruptcy, supra note 99.

[175]. Tung, supra note 127, at 178–80 (discussing the impact that lenders can independently have on the governance of corporations).

[176]. Id. at 178.

[177]. This is exactly what state regulation of corporate governance is designed to allow.  State corporate law is made up of enabling statutes with many default provisions designed to let incorporating parties design the best governance regime for their business.  Romano, supra note 119.

[178]. See, e.g., Harwell Wells, The Birth of Corporate Governance, 33 Seattle U. L. Rev. 1247 (2010) (discussing the changes, over time, of the corporation, and corporate governance’s reaction to those changes).

[179]. Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 141(a) (2010).

[180]. NYSE Amex Section § 802, Corporate Governance Requirements (2010), available at http://wallstreet.cch.com/AMEXTools/PlatformViewer.asp
?searched=1&selectednode=chp_1_1_8_1&CiRestriction=governance&manual=%2Famex%2Fcompanyguide%2Famex-company-guide%2F.

[181]. 15 U.S.C. § 78j-1 (2006).

[182]. Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 141(a) (2010) (emphasis added).

[183]. If one were to use an online service to establish a corporation in Delaware, one would find a notation requiring that a board of directors be formed.  See, e.g., Incorporating 101, Harv. Bus. Servs., Inc., http://www.delawareinc.com/101/index.cfm?pageid=10068 (last visited Sept. 16, 2011) (stating that, as a formality, the formation of a board of directors is required to establish a corporation in Delaware).

[184]. Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 141(c)(2) (2010) (allowing the board to designate a committee and stating that such committees “shall have and may exercise all the powers and authority of the board of directors in the management of the business and affairs of the corporation”); see also Zapata Corp. v. Maldonado, 430 A.2d 779 (Del. 1981) (considering the business judgment of the corporation’s directors as delegated to a special litigation committee).

[185]. Grimes v. Donald, 673 A.2d 1207 (Del. 1996) (holding, in part, that a board of directors is permitted to delegate its decision-making authority to the firm’s CEO provided it has the power to do so).

[186]. Stout, supra note 77, at 669.

[187]. Id. at 698.

[188]. Id. at 669.

[189]. Id.

[190]. Id. at 698–701 (arguing that a mediating board should be favored as opposed to an independent monitoring one but preferring board decision making to shareholder authority); Bainbridge, Director Primacy, supra note 12 (maintaining that boards should be able to exercise discretion over corporate business without regard to preferred shareholder means because shareholders lack knowledge of corporate affairs and the necessary sophistication to make profit-maximizing business decisions).

[191]. Stout, supra note 77, at 669.

[192]. NYSE Listed Company Manual § 303A.01, available at http://nysemanual.nyse.com/LCMTools/PlatformViewer.asp?searched=1&selectednode=chp%5F1%5F4%5F3%5F2&CiRestriction=independent+AND+director&manual=%2Flcm%2Fsections%2Flcm%2Dsections%2F (last visited Sept. 16, 2011).

[193]. Id. § 303A.02(a).

[194]. Id.

[195]. Id.

[196]. Pub. L. No. 107-204, 116 Stat. 745 (2002) (codified in scattered sections of 15 and 18 U.S.C.).

[197]. 15 U.S.C. § 78j-1(i) (2010).

[198]. Id. § 78j-3.

[199]. Id. § 78j-1(m)(3); id. § 78j-3(a).

[200]. Id. § 78j-1(m)(3).

[201]. See supra Part I.A; see also Langevoort, supra note 10, at 800; Romano, supra note 108, at 1526.

[202]. See Romano, supra note 108, at 1523.

[203]. Id. at 1529.

[204]. R. Franklin Balotti & Jesse A. Finkelstein, Delaware Law of Corporation and Business Organization § 4.16 (2008); see also Anadarko Petroleum Corp. v. Panhandle E. Corp., 545 A.2d 1171, 1174 (Del. 1988) (“It is a basic principle of Delaware General Corporation Law that directors are subject to the fundamental fiduciary duties of loyalty and disinterestedness.  Specifically, directors cannot stand on both sides of the transaction nor derive any personal benefit through self-dealing.”).

[205]. Stephen M. Bainbridge, Corporation Law and Economics 519 (2002).

[206]. Id.

[207]. Id. at 520.

[208]. Id. at 531–37.

[209]. See generally M. Todd Henderson, Insider Trading and CEO Pay, 64 Vand. L. Rev. 505 (2011).

[210]. Jill E. Fisch, Securities Intermediaries and the Separation of Ownership from Control, 33 Seattle U. L. Rev. 877, 877–88 (2010); Tamar Frankel, The New Financial Assets: Separating Ownership from Control, 33 Seattle U. L. Rev. 931, 933 (2010) (“[D]uring the past thirty years, fundamental financial concepts and designs have been warped or eliminated.”).

Article in PDF Form

By: Mira Ganor*

Abstract

Studies of management’s disregard of the will of the shareholders have focused on combinations of entrenchment mechanisms and special governance structures.  However, management’s power to issue stock—a fundamental element of the ability of management to control the corporation regardless of the will of the shareholders—has received scarce attention.  This Article highlights the significance of the power to issue stock: when managers choose to ignore the will of the majority of the shareholders or when managers choose to circumvent the veto power of the minority shareholders, they often take advantage of their power to issue stock.  A top-up option, for example, which is studied in this Article, is contingent upon the managers’ ability to issue shares and dilute the voting power of the dissenting minority shareholders.  The poison pill is also contingent upon the managers’ ability to dilute a hostile bidder by issuing shares to the shareholders.  The ability of managers to use new stock issuances as a shareholder-circumventing mechanism is particularly important.  It plays a key role in the management’s arsenal and provides an incentive for managers to reserve this unique power and refrain from diminishing it by, for example, replacing equity-based compensation and equity financing with less efficient choices.  This Article explores the key power of managers to issue stock as well as the current and potential limitations on this power.  One such limitation is the size of the authorized capital of the corporation, which provides a ceiling for the total number of shares that can be issued.  The ratio of authorized non-outstanding shares to the issued and outstanding shares—what I shall call the “excess ratio”—is an indicator of the magnitude of the managers’ power to issue stock.  A study of the excess ratio reveals that corporations go public with a high excess ratio—the number of unissued authorized shares is more than three times the number of issued shares.  Further results of the study of the excess ratio are analyzed in this Article.

Introduction

A company’s board of directors is entrusted with the power to issue stock.  Shareholder approval is usually not required for this basic managerial prerogative.[1]  Conventional issuances of stock by the board of directors generally serve valid business goals, such as financing the firm’s operations and motivating employees.  Raising funds for the company’s operations can be done through equity financing in which the investor gives the company money in exchange for an equity stake in the company.  Aligning the interests of recipients of the issued stock, such as employees and service providers, with the interests of the company is another business-driven motivation to issue stock.

A direct outcome of any issuance of shares is the dilution of existing shareholders.  Voting dilution occurs when the existing shareholder owns a lower percentage of the company than she had before the new issue of stock, and thus her voting rights represent a lower percentage of the total shareholder votes.  Voting dilution can occur even if the value of the shares of the existing shareholder remains the same and is undiluted by the issuance of new shares.  If the new shareholder purchases her shares for a fair consideration, it does not affect the value of the existing shareholders.  The voting rights of the existing shareholder, however, will be diluted if she does not participate in the new issuance pro-rata to her percentage holding prior to the issuance.  After the issuance of new shares, the old shareholder possesses a smaller percentage of the company, yet the company is worth more.[2]  If the consideration received for the new shares is lower than the intrinsic fair value of these shares, then the economic value of the old shareholders is diluted and their stake in the company is worth less after the issuance of the new shares.

This byproduct of issuing new shares, diluting the existing shareholders, can become the intended outcome of the managers.  They can use their power to issue shares to dilute the voting rights of the shareholders or to dilute the economic value of shares.  The managers can take advantage of this power to dilute shareholders to advance inefficient self-promoting goals.  Using the power to issue shares to circumvent the voting power of the shareholders can take several forms.

Perhaps the most common and renowned use of the power to issue shares is the poison pill.  Poison pills refer to shareholder-rights plans that enable managers to thwart a hostile takeover.[3]  These rights plans allow the existing shareholders, but not the raider, to acquire a substantial amount of new shares at an exceptionally low cost.[4]  The expected result of the poison pill, the dilution of the economic value of the raider, serves as a deterrent to a hostile raider.  The managers’ ability to dilute the hostile bidder prevents the takeover and entrenches the managers despite the support of the shareholders who may favor the hostile takeover.

The combination of several entrenchment mechanisms, and in particular the existence of a staggered board along with a poison pill, is especially effective in preventing a hostile takeover, even if the shareholders favor the acquisition.[5]  Yet, even a poison pill by itself can stop hostile takeovers.  For example, a poison pill helped Yahoo’s management in the famous failed attempt by Microsoft to complete a hostile takeover of Yahoo.[6]  Yahoo’s poison pill enabled its managers to dilute a hostile bidder by issuing cheap shares to the existing shareholders only.[7]  This poison pill rendered the takeover economically prohibitive ex ante.

The poison pill, along with a few other entrenchment mechanisms, has been at the center of the conventional focus of research on managers’ efforts to entrench themselves.[8]  The power to issue stock, a fundamental component of the poison pill, was not put at the center of the debate.  It is the power to issue stock, however, that enables the managers to entrench themselves using anti-takeover mechanisms such as the poison pill and the white squire[9] when shareholders are in favor of a sale.  The power to issue stock also helps managers sell the company when they are personally interested in the sale despite significant shareholder opposition.[10]

Top-up options, for example, which are studied in this Article, are powerful tools that have increasingly been used to dilute the voting power of opposing shareholders in takeovers supported by the board of directors.[11]  The grant of a top-up option as part of a takeover may allow for the consummation of a quick short-form merger without a shareholder meeting and despite the opposition of a significant number of the shareholders in excess of the statutory ceiling of ten percent of the shares.[12]  The effect of a top-up option is that a management-friendly bidder faces only a truncated supply curve at the tender offer.  This is because a top-up option lowers the percentage of shares needed to be tendered in order to have a successful outcome.  In addition, the speed of the takeover process makes it harder for a competing bidder to launch an opposing bid.  Like the poison pill, top-up options are contingent upon the managers’ ability to issue a nontrivial number of shares and thus dilute the voting power of the dissenting minority shareholders.

Therefore, through new share issuances the managers have the ability to disregard the will of the shareholders and diminish the shareholder voting power.  Managers can abuse this power for personal gain when they want to entrench themselves and prevent an efficient takeover of the company.  This is the general criticism of mechanisms like poison pills and white squires[13] that can be used by self-interested managers to prevent a hostile takeover.  Similarly, managers may want to push forward an acquisition despite significant shareholder opposition because the managers may stand to benefit from the transaction personally, either because they are related to the acquirer or because they expect to receive personal benefits from the sale, such as retention bonuses or perpetual thrones.[14]

To be sure, not all usages of the power to issue shares are inefficient and undesirable.[15]  In addition to equity financing and equity compensation, even indirect business usages aimed at influencing the outcome of the shareholder vote, such as a poison pill or a top-up option, can be desirable given certain scenarios.[16]  Yet, although there may be some cases in which managers’ use of their power to issue stock in order to dictate the shareholder vote is efficient, the existence of this power to issue stock and its limits[17] are likely to influence managerial decisions in inefficient ways that are in part discussed in this Article.[18]

In particular, in an effort to maintain their power to issue stock, managers have an incentive to refrain from using stock for other business needs.  This is because the managers’ power to issue stock is limited and is mainly capped by the authorized capitalization set in the certificate of incorporation of the company.[19]  As a result, managers have an incentive not to deplete the reserve of issuable shares, which may lead to excessive debt financing and overuse of monetary compensation.

This raises the question of whether or not the managers should have a restricted power to issue stock that would only allow them to issue stock for ordinary, nonorganic uses such as raising funds and aligning interests.  The managers could be completely barred from issuing stock unilaterally, without the approval of the shareholders.[20]  Conversely, should the managers be allowed to use the power to issue shares to influence the shareholders’ vote without any limitation?  In Maryland, for example, managers may be allowed to issue an unlimited number of shares for any purpose.[21]

In between these two extreme possible governance systems, there can be a policy that allows the managers to issue stock subject to certain limitations.  For example, the current Delaware regime restricts the managers’ power to issue stock and requires a cap on the total number of shares that can be issued without shareholder approval.[22]  This cap has to be included as part of the company’s certificate of incorporation.[23]  A nuance of this regime links the maximum number of shares that can be issued without shareholder approval to the number of shares that are already issued by setting the maximum as a percentage of the number of issued shares.[24]

Preemptive rights represent another possible restriction on the power to issue stock.  Preemptive rights allow the shareholders to participate in any issuance of shares pro rata to their percentage holding and thus can prevent dilution of the existing shareholders.[25]

The remainder of the Article proceeds as follows: Part I describes the shareholder power to issue shares, including the phenomenon of granting top-up options, and presents examples of such grants that illustrate the self-interest that has motivated these grants.  Current limitations on the issuance of stock are described in this Part.  Part I also examines the costs and benefits of the power while discussing possible incentive effects.  Finally, the results of an empirical study of the excess ratio are presented in Part II, and the final Part concludes.

I.  Issuance of Shares

Stockholders’ ownership of the corporation manifests itself in shares that give the stockholders various powers.  Most notably, the shares are assigned the right to vote on certain resolutions and the right to transfer and sell the shares.  Voting and selling shares are the conventional tools that stockholders have to control the managers and the corporation.[26]

The desirability and extent of the power of the shareholders to control the company through shareholder votes and sales of their stock has been vastly debated.  Most notably, Lucian Bebchuk in his salient work on corporate governance calls for an increase in the shareholder power and a decrease in managerial control.[27]  Other commentators have critiqued Bebchuk’s view, raising doubts regarding the desirability of shareholder primacy.[28]  In their renowned work, Henry Hu and Bernie Black exposed a major weakness of shareholder voting by demonstrating that share ownership and voting rights can easily be decoupled.[29]

Yet both the possibility of managers abusing their position as agents of the shareholders and the limits to the existing power of the shareholders to monitor the managers effectively are central to the quest of improving corporate governance, regardless of the answer to the question of the optimal level of shareholder control of the company.  As this Article will show, the power to issue stock in its current format enables managers to circumvent the will of the shareholders and promote the managers’ own self-interest at the shareholders’ expense.  To be sure, even opponents of the view that calls for enhanced shareholder power will support lowering agency costs and restricting self-enhancing and self-promoting managerial behavior that comes at the expense of the shareholders.

This Article focuses on strategic issuances of new shares in order to control the shareholder vote.  This is an abuse of managers’ power that creates agency costs by using the shareholder vote, the tool that is supposed to help shareholders monitor managers.  Issuance of shares can help entrench the managers when the shareholders would rather sell the company.[30]  When it serves the self-interest of the managers, issuances of shares can also help sell the company despite significant opposition of shareholders who are not interested in selling.[31]  As we shall see, the new shares may help the managers circumvent the will of the shareholders and promote the managers’ own interests.

Issuance of new shares has a powerful effect on existing shareholders, as it dilutes their holdings.  A shareholder’s voting rights are diluted by the issuance of new shares unless she participates in the new issuance at least pro rata to her old percentage holding in the company and thus maintains at least the same percentage of the company as she did prior to the new issuance of shares.  Issuance of shares can also result in an economic dilution of the existing shareholders.  Economic dilution occurs when the value of the shareholder’s stake in the company declines because of the newly-issued shares.[32]  The value of the existing shares will decline when the consideration received for the new shares is lower than their true value.[33]

The following example illustrates the dilution effect.  Suppose the value of a company is $100 and the shareholders of the company have a total of 100 shares.  A new shareholder pays the company $50 in exchange for 100 newly-issued shares, a price of $0.50 per share.  The new value of the company following the share issuance transaction is the sum of the old value of the company (i.e., $100) and the consideration the company received from the new shareholder (i.e., $50), equaling a total of $150.

The newly-issued shares give the new shareholder the rights to half of the company.  The old shareholders now own only half of the company because the other half belongs to the new shareholder (who owns 100 shares out of a total of 200 shares).  Thus, the voting rights of the old shareholders are diluted from 100% of the rights to vote to only 50% of the voting rights of the company.  In addition, the value of the shares owned by the old shareholders decreases to half of the new value of the company and is now worth only $75 (half of $150).  However, if the new shareholder pays fair value for the newly-issued shares ($100 for half of the company or $1 per share) then, following this fair transaction, the old shareholders’ stake in the company remains $100 (or half of $200) which is the new value of the company after receipt of $100 as consideration for the new shares.  The old shareholder now owns only half of the company, but half of a company that is worth twice as much as it was before the stock issuance transaction.

The value of the shares of the old shareholders remains the same, undiluted by the issuance of new shares if the new shares are issued for their intrinsic fair market value.  Yet the voting rights of the old shareholders are diluted even if the consideration the company receives for the new shares is fair, as long as the old shareholders do not participate in the new issue pro rata to their percentage holding prior to the issuance.

An examination of the contours of the managerial power to issue stock aids in understanding the agency cost related to this power.  Subpart A describes the rules governing the right to issue shares.  Subpart B and Subpart C describe usages of new stock issuances.  Subpart D reviews noncontroversial usages of stock issuances, and the latter Subparts discuss usages of the power to issue stock that can be questionable and that affect the control of the corporation.

A.            Rules Governing the Issuance of Stock

Generally, the board can issue stock without shareholder approval.[34]  This power, however, relies on the availability of sufficiently authorized but unissued shares.[35]  A company cannot issue more shares than the number of authorized shares of its capital that are not already issued.  Thus, the authorized capital sets the upper limit.

The size of the authorized capital, however, is not controlled by the managers alone.  The certificate of incorporation includes the amount of authorized shares of the company.[36]  Consequently, the shareholders must approve any changes in the number of authorized shares because the shareholders’ approval is needed in order to change the charter of the company.[37]

The number of authorized shares set out in the certificate of incorporation of the company is a statutory upper limit to the total number of shares the managers can issue.[38]  Managers can continue to issue shares as long as the total number of issued shares is smaller than the number of authorized shares.[39]  The number of shares that the managers can issue without receiving the shareholders’ approval equals the difference between the number of authorized shares and the number of shares already issued.[40]  Keeping everything else constant, the higher the number of authorized shares, the higher the number of shares that the mangers can issue.  Similarly, everything else equal, the lower the number of existing issued shares, the higher the number of shares that the managers can issue.

However, while the managers cannot unilaterally control the number of authorized shares, they have discretion about whether to issue new shares.[41]  Thus, in order to evaluate whether the number of authorized shares effectively restricts managers’ power to issue shares, we need to look also at managers’ ability to influence the number of already issued and outstanding shares.

Managers can refrain from issuing new shares to keep the number of shares that they can issue high in order to be able to issue more shares in the future.  For example, the managers may choose to finance the firm’s activities with debt rather than equity.[42]  Similarly, managers can opt to pay cash rather than to grant equity-based compensation to employees in order to keep the unissued share reserve intact.[43]

Another way for managers to affect the number of shares they can issue is through share repurchase.  In addition to new shares that are not yet issued, managers can use shares that had been issued but were bought back by the company, and thus are no longer outstanding, to sell shares without running afoul of the upper limit set by the authorized capital.  When the company repurchases shares, it increases the number of issued-but-not-outstanding shares, which are commonly referred to as treasury shares.[44]

When a company repurchases shares, however, it needs to pay for these shares.[45]  Paying for these shares can come at the expense of alternative uses for the company’s funds.  Conversely, managers who wish to conduct share repurchases may engage in excessive cash retention in anticipation of an opportunity for the share repurchase.[46]  If, however, the company independently plans to make a distribution to the shareholders, the managers may choose to do so by conducting a share repurchase rather than by distributing dividends.  By choosing share repurchases, the managers increase the number of shares that may be issued without shareholder approval.  There is evidence that suggests that managers opt for share repurchases instead of using dividend distributions.[47]

Indeed, the increase in the pool of shares available for employee stock option grants is one of a few advantages attributed to share repurchases over dividends.[48]  The repurchased shares can be used to compensate the employees.  Yet doubt has been cast on the need for share repurchases to conduct employee stock option grants that enhance shareholder value.[49]  Arguably, the shareholders would approve the requested increase of the number of authorized shares in order to allow such option grants.[50]

However, when the number of unissued authorized shares of the company is just enough for the option grants, the managers may be reluctant to use the surplus of authorized-but-unissued shares for the option grants.  Such grants may not leave a sufficient number of authorized-but-unissued shares that may be needed for other purposes that enhance the personal interests of the managers, such as entrenchment.  Unlike shareholder-serving employee option grants, certain manager-serving transactions are unlikely to receive the support of the shareholders and may not obtain the shareholder approval needed to increase the number of authorized shares.  Similarly, where the number of unissued authorized shares is just enough for the option grants, the shareholders may not agree to increase the authorized capital at the time of the option grants, knowing that it is not needed for the option grant but that the increase will allow the managers to issue shares in the future for different purposes without going back to the shareholders for approval.

Thus, the limit on the amount of shares that managers can issue without the approval of the shareholders influences the managers’ choice between share repurchase and dividends and adds an additional motivation in favor of share repurchases.  Yet, in spite of certain benefits attributed to share repurchases, there is evidence that suggests dividends are, at least in some cases, significantly more efficient than share repurchases and involve lower transaction costs.[51]

In addition to the quantitative limitation on the managerial power to issue stock, issuances of stock are subject to consideration requirements.  The Delaware requirements, however, are very lenient and allow for the issuance of shares in exchange for any benefit to the corporation.[52]  Moreover, the Delaware statute gives full deference to the directors’ judgment regarding the value of the consideration absent actual fraud.[53]

Another important mechanism that can reduce the number of shares that are issued and outstanding is a reverse stock split.  In a reverse stock split the company replaces the outstanding shares of all the shareholders with a lower number of new shares.  For example, in a reverse stock split, with a ratio of 1:10, every ten shares are replaced with only one new share.  Since a reverse stock split decreases the number of outstanding shares, it can increase the number of authorized but not outstanding shares of the company.  However, as with the case of changing the number of authorized shares, in Delaware a reverse stock split requires shareholder approval.[54]  Thus, the managers cannot unilaterally use a reverse stock split to increase their power to issue stock.

B.            Conventional Business-Operation-Related Reasons to Issue Shares

When the company needs funds for its operations it can generally consider financing either through equity or through debt.[55]  Limited access to equity or debt can dictate the capital structure of the corporation and thus leave no alternative for the managers but to elect the only available option.  For example, in the early stages of the corporation, high-tech startups usually do not have any tangible assets that can serve as collateral for a loan.[56]  Consequently, the ability of a startup founder to raise money for her risky enterprise through debt is practically nonexistent.[57]  In such corporations, financing is limited to equity financing and issuances of stock are crucial for the corporation’s continued operations.

To the extent that both equity and debt financing are available to the corporation, the management chooses the level of each of the financing sources and sets the capital structure of the corporation.  The managerial choice between these two sources of financing and its effect on the corporation have been studied by finance scholars.[58]  These studies show that the value of the corporation is sensitive to changes in the capital structure of the corporation, given real world assumptions of taxes, transaction costs, and inefficient markets.[59]  Thus, even when debt financing is available, it may be more efficient for the corporation to use equity to raise capital for its operations.  For example, debt may be available only if the corporation undertakes to agree to certain restrictive covenants that are designed to protect the lenders.[60]  Since the lenders do not share in the upside of the corporation, these covenants may be overly restrictive.[61]  Thus, the corporation’s ability to issue stock can be central for operations because the stock issuance enables the corporation to receive needed funds.

Grants of shares are also commonly used in another ordinary business-enhancing practice aimed at creating a common interest between the recipients of the new shares and the company.[62]  Equity-based compensation is the main example for this use of shares.[63]  When an employee receives equity in the company, she receives an incentive to increase the value of the company.[64]  Issuing shares is useful when the company is interested in motivating a person to increase the value of the company’s shares.  If the person participates in the upside of the company and is negatively affected when the company is doing poorly, it increases her interest in the success of the company.  To be sure, equity-based compensation can be vulnerable to managerial manipulation that weakens the incentive effect of the equity.[65]  However, commentators have shown that properly designed limitations, such as vesting schemes, unwinding limitations, and hedging restrictions, can ensure a closer connection between the equity compensation and long-term performance.[66]

However, neither raising money nor compensating employees has to be equity based.  Instead, the company can often use debt financing to support its operations and use cash to pay its employees.  Furthermore, when the company has liquidity constraints, the managers do not have to use equity even when they have no alternative to equity financing.  Rather, they can choose to scale down the business.  Reluctant to issue a considerable amount of new equity, the managers can revert to downsizing the operations of the company while forgoing growth opportunities and profitable projects.[67]  Similarly, paying cash to compensate employees through salaries and monetary bonuses and reducing the workforce are alternatives to the use of employee equity compensation.

C.            Control Related Uses of the Power to Issue Shares

The previous Subpart showed that managers can use the power to issue stock for basic business operations of the company.  This Subpart looks at more special uses of the power to issue stock that do not involve the daily operations of the company but rather relate to the ability of the mangers to control fundamental changes to the corporation.

1. The Poison Pill

The poison pill, a shareholders’ rights plan, is an effective antitakeover mechanism that enables the managers to block and deter hostile takeovers.[68]  The poison pill dilutes both the value of the raider’s shares and the voting power of the shares.[69]  The poison pill creates a credible threat to distribute new shares to all the shareholders except to the raider for a radically low price.[70]  The target managers’ ability to credibly threaten the issuance of a large number of significantly undervalued stocks makes a hostile takeover economically prohibitive.

A simple example may illustrate the mechanics of the poison pill.  Suppose the company has 100 million shares issued and outstanding.  The shares are publicly traded at $10 per share.  Suppose further that the management has put in place a poison pill that is triggered when a hostile acquirer accumulates 10% of the equity of the company.  Assuming that under the terms of the poison pill, once it is triggered, all the shareholders except for the hostile acquirer obtain the right to purchase one share for each share they own for half the price—then they will pay only $5 per share.

A hostile acquirer buys 10% of the shares of the company, 10 million shares, for $10 per share, for a total investment of $100 million.  This acquisition triggers the poison pill and the management distributes to all the shareholders, except for the hostile acquirer, new shares at a rate of one new share for each existing share.  The company distributes a total of 90 million new shares.  After the distribution, the company has 190 million shares issued and outstanding, of which the hostile acquirer owns 10 million shares.

In this example, the hostile acquirer’s stake decreased from 10% of the company to only 5.26% of the company.[71]  In addition, after the distribution of the new shares following the triggering of the poison pill, the company’s total value is $1450 million, the sum of the original $1 billion plus the consideration received for the new shares of $5 per each of the 90 million new shares or a total of $450 million.  As a result, the value of the hostile acquirer’s investment is now worth only $76.3 million,[72] almost a quarter less than the original investment.

The above example demonstrates that triggering a poison pill is very expensive to a hostile bidder.  The example also demonstrates that the mechanism of the poison pill relies on the managers’ ability to issue shares upon the triggering event.  In fact, in order to have a strong dilutive effect on the hostile bidder, the management needs to issue a very significant number of shares relative to the already issued shares.  In the above example, the company only issued one share for every share already issued, or a 1:1 ratio.  In a seminal study of poison pills, Guhan Subramanian reports that in the sample of large publicly traded software companies the average poison pill provided for thirteen shares of the target for each existing share, or a ratio of 13:1.[73]  These considerably larger ratios require a nontrivial, large number of authorized-but-unissued shares to enable the exercise of the rights under the poison pill.[74]

The desirability of the poison pill has been extensively debated.[75]  Supporters of the poison pill approve of the managers’ ability to prevent, or at least delay, a hostile acquisition of the corporation, arguing that a managerial veto may help enhance shareholder welfare.[76]  Holders of the opposite view, however, voice strong concerns about the significant agency costs that a poison pill creates.[77]  Managers may use a poison pill to block an efficient acquisition in order to entrench themselves.[78]  The managers may also use the poison pill to negotiate for personal benefits from the acquirer.[79]  A body of empirical studies supports the opponents of the poison pill and shows that the poison pill results in a significant negative effect on shareholder wealth.[80]

2. The Top-Up Option

Another nontrivial use of the managers’ power to issue stock, the top-up option, also arises in the context of a change in control following an acquisition of the company.  Like the poison pill, a top-up option is granted to ensure the outcome the managers want to promote, regardless of the shareholders’ vote.[81]  Unlike a poison pill, a top-up option is used when the management prefers the acquisition;[82] the top-up option is designed to force through an acquisition and a subsequent shareholder freeze-out despite the opposition from a large block of the minority shareholders.[83]  Like the poison pill, as demonstrated in this Part, the top-up option is likely to involve agency costs and diminish shareholder wealth.[84]

A top-up option is a choice that the board of a company gives to a bidder who wants to acquire the company.[85]  After receipt of the option, the bidder conducts a tender offer.[86]  If the tender offer is successful and the bidder acquires at least a majority of the shares,[87] then the top-up option allows the bidder to proceed with the takeover of the company and buy directly from the company newly-issued shares that, together with the shares tendered in the tender offer, will represent 90% of the issued and outstanding shares of the company.  Owning 90% of the capital of the company allows the bidder to buy out the nontendering shareholders using a freeze-out short-form merger.[88]  A short-form merger does not require a meeting or a vote of the shareholders and leaves the shareholders with only appraisal rights as their sole recourse.[89]  In Delaware, a short-form merger only requires owning 90% of each class of shares of the company.[90]

a.  Mechanism

The following example illustrates the mechanics of the top-up option and the resulting implications to the company’s capitalization.  Suppose there are 100 shares issued and outstanding before the tender offer.  Assume the bidder received 50 shares in the tender offer, which also represent 50% of the total issued and outstanding shares of the company.  Following the exercise of a top-up option the company will issue new shares to the bidder, who will own 90% of the number of all outstanding shares at that time.  How many shares should the company issue to the bidder?  In this example the company has to issue 400 new shares to the bidder, increasing the total number of issued and outstanding shares from 100 to 500 shares.  After the exercise of the option the bidder will own 450 shares, comprised of 50 shares that she purchased in the tender offer from the shareholders and another 400 shares that the company issued directly to the bidder following the exercise of the top-up option.  The 450 shares held by the bidder after the exercise of the top-up option make up 90% of the new total number of shares, which includes 500 shares.  The following table summarizes the capitalization of the company.

 

Table 1: Company Capitalization

 

Bidder’s Shares

Non-tendering Shareholders

Total Number of Shares

Bidder’s Percentage

Tender Offer 50 50 100 50%
Top-Up Option 400 0 400 100%
Total 450 50 500 90%

 

More generally, to reach 90% of the shares, the company needs to issue the bidder ten times the difference between the percentage she has acquired and the desired 90%.  In the previous example, the difference was 40%—the bidder acquired 50% in the tender offer and thus was 40% short of 90%.  Ten times the difference of 40% is 400%.  The formula that can be used to derive the number of shares that the company needs to issue if a top-up option is exercised can thus be illustrated algebraically as:

X  =  (90% – Y) × 10

X represents how many shares the company shall issue to the bidder in exchange for the exercise of the top-up option as a percentage of the outstanding shares immediately before the exercise of the option, or 400% in our example.  Y represents the percentage of outstanding stock the bidder owns following the tender offer, or 50% in our example.[91]  Thus, as the formula demonstrates, a large number of shares is needed to use a top-up option.

Once the bidder exercises the top-up option, she needs to buy the new shares from the company and pay the same price for these shares that she paid in the tender offer.  A lower price will not represent a fair market price and may be easily challenged since the tender offer price establishes a fair market price for the shares.  As the example above illustrates, a large number of shares is issued when the top-up option is exercised; hence, the consideration that the bidder should pay the company for these shares is substantial.  However, the consideration for the shares can be, and often is, paid with an unsecured note except for a small part, which represents the par value of the shares.[92]  Following the short-form merger, the unsecured note issued in exchange for the shares is nullified because after this merger the holder of the note is combined with the issuer of the note and they become one.[93]

Therefore, the top-up option, like the poison pill, requires a significant number of authorized-but-unissued shares to allow for the management to issue shares as part of this scheme.

b.  Agency Costs

The power to issue stock to grant a top-up option to a potential bidder can be abused by self-interested managers and hurt the shareholders’ wealth.  The performance of a short-form merger after the tender offer not only allows for a speedy merger because there is no need for a shareholder meeting, a proxy statement, or a shareholder vote, but it also restricts the remedies available to the dissenting shareholders.[94]  Statutorily, the short-form merger is restricted to a situation in which the acquirer owns more than a simple majority of the shares.  In Delaware, the requirement is at least 90% of the company’s issued shares.[95]  The short-form merger protects against holdups by a very small number of shareholders who together own up to 10% of the company’s stock.  The top-up option artificially transforms the acquirer into a holder of 90% of the shares, while the dissenting shareholders constituted more than the maximum statutory threshold of 10% before the exercise of the option.[96]

A dissenting shareholder’s only remedy in a short-form merger is appraisal and not entire fairness.[97]  Thus, the use of the top-up option also protects the board that serves after the tender—the board does not need to perform a statutory long-form merger, which could have subjected the directors to a fairness review.[98]  In this manner the bidder can go ahead with the acquisition even in the face of sizable shareholder opposition.

To be sure, in exchange for the grant of the top-up option the managers may have succeeded in negotiating better terms for the selling shareholders—a higher purchase price.  However, the managers’ interest in the acquisition may be influenced by personal interests.  The managers may be connected to the acquirer through a business association or other relationship with the acquirer.  The acquirer herself may have been a member of the board, and as a result, the acquirer and other managers may have developed close ties because they served together on the board for a long time as colleagues.

The managers may also stand to gain from the acquisition directly.  For example, a promise from the acquirer to grant the target’s directors perpetual thrones (i.e., nominations to the board of directors of the acquirer, may personally incentivize the managers to favor the acquisition).[99]  The managers may have used their negotiation powers to extract benefits for themselves, which may include lucrative retention plans and retention bonuses as well as perpetual thrones.  In exchange for arrangements that benefit the managers, however, the shareholders may well have been deprived of the ability to extract a higher price from the acquirer.

The party interested in acquiring the company and freezing out all of the shareholders has a choice.  For one, the acquirer can ask the managers for a top-up option and reward them for their support.  Under this option, it is sufficient for the acquirer to receive only 50% of the shares in the tender offer and use the top-up option to own 90% of the shares.  Alternatively, the acquirer can conduct a tender offer without the support of the managers and without a top-up option, with the intent of receiving 90% of the shares immediately in the tender offer itself.

Convincing 50% of the shareholders to sell is not the same as convincing 90% of the shareholders.  A bidder must offer all the shareholders the same price per share.[100]  Since the acquirer faces diverse shareholders, rather than only one seller, she likely faces an upward-sloping supply curve,[101] meaning that more shareholders are willing to sell their shares at a higher price than for a lower price.  The higher the offer price used in the tender offer, the higher the number of shareholders willing to tender their shares at the tender offer.  The result is that if the bidder needs to receive more shares in the tender offer, she also has to increase the price offered.

The top-up option, however, essentially truncates the supply curve that the bidder in the tender offer faces and allows her to offer a lower price—the price that will clear only 50% of the shares rather than the higher 90%.  The remaining shareholders who did not want to sell for the low tender offer price will receive the same price paid in the tender offer in the freeze out short-form merger that will follow the exercise of the top-up option.[102]  Thus, it seems that the receipt of the top-up option allows the acquirer to buy the company for a lower price, which hurts the wealth of the shareholders.

The following example illustrates the effect of the top-up option on the price of the tender offer.  Suppose the company has four shareholders each owning 25% of the equity of the company.  Shareholder A values the company’s shares at $10 per share; shareholder B thinks the shares are worth $11; shareholder C assumes that the right price is $12; and shareholder D, being very optimistic about the future of the company, estimates the price of the share at $13.  The table below lists the values that each of the four shareholders assign to the company’s shares.  The holders of 50% of the shares will agree to sell the company for a price of $11 per share; however, the holders of 90% of the shares will not agree to sell the company for $11 per share.  If the holders of 90% of the shares must consent to the sale, the shareholders should be offered at least $13 per share.

Table 2: Shareholders’ Value of Company’s Shares

 

Shareholder

Price per Share

Accumulated Percentage

A $10 25%
B $11 50%
C $12 75%
D $13 100%

 

On occasion, the holder of the median share may agree to sell for a fair price; however, many times shareholders waiting for an opportunity to dump their shares form the bottom of the supply curve.  They will sell even at a lower price than the shares are worth, since they cannot do so in the open market because their sale of the shares would cause the price to drastically go down, causing them further loss.  A sale of a significant stake may negatively affect the market price.  The identity of the seller may also negatively affect the price where, for example, the seller is a sophisticated investor or is in a business relationship with the company and the market is likely to view such a sale as a negative sign.[103]  Thus, the price the holder of the median share is willing to accept may not represent a fair price.

It may be efficient to let the deal through at a lower price so that the shareholders waiting to liquidate their holdings may do so even at the expense of the other shareholders who would like to receive a more equitable value for their shares.  However, it may also be the case that it is not just a zero-sum game in which the acquirer wins because she pays less in a transfer of wealth from the shareholders to the bidder.  It may well be that the transaction is inefficient because the acquirer is going to run the operations of the company less efficiently than the company was run as a standalone operation before the acquisition.  In this case, the acquirer truly values the company less than the nontendering shareholders.

The appraisal rights of the dissenting shareholders are designed to ensure that these shareholders receive a fair value for their shares.[104]  Nevertheless, it is well known that the judicial appraisal remedy offers but a weak defense.[105]  Calculating the fair value of a share is not an easy task.  It is based on several assumptions that are hard to predict, such as the appropriate future interest rates and future exchange rates, and it involves forecasting methodologies that are far from being an accurate science.  Efficient markets help reveal the fair market value of shares.[106]  Yet, markets are rarely perfectly efficient, and indeed, acquirers do not pay the shareholders the price at which the shares are traded in the markets.  This affects the predictability of the outcome of the appraisal process and thus increases the risk of a small individual shareholder.

Furthermore, the appraisal litigation procedure involves strict requirements of notification deadlines and a short period for filing.[107]  On the other hand, the appraisal procedure itself may take years, is expensive, complex, and involves the risk of the acquirer becoming insolvent by the time of the resolution of the litigation.[108]  Thus, given the complexity and costs associated with the appraisal procedure, shareholders who oppose the short-form merger may be better off accepting the offered consideration and may choose not to use their right to a judicial appraisal even where they believe they are not fairly compensated for their shares.

The case of Gholl v. eMachines is an example of a successful appraisal action that included a top-up option.[109]  eMachines, a seller of personal computers and Internet services, went public in March 2000 at a price of $9 per share.[110]  By the end of 2000, eMachines was doing poorly and its stock was trading at only $0.5 per share.[111]  In 2001, in an effort to reform the business, the company hired a new management team, replacing its top ranking officials (both its CEO and COO) who introduced a new business plan.[112]

By mid-2001 the company’s business had completely turned around, despite the market perception to the contrary.[113]  The board considered its alternatives, including selling the company, and for that purpose started a bidding process.[114]  However, the only potential acquirer who offered to buy the company offered to pay less for it than the value of the company’s cash; thus, the company rejected the offer and ended the bidding process in mid-September.[115]

In October, one of the founders of the company, and a member of its board, submitted a low offer to purchase the company for less than the last offer made by the outside bidder less than three months before.[116]  The board contacted the outside bidder, and a bidding war ensued between the director and the outside bidder in mid-November.[117]  On November 16, the board announced that all final bids should be submitted within two days.[118]  The director won the bid, offering $4.2 million less than the company’s cash value and ignoring the value of the company’s operations.[119]  The price was set at $1.06 per share.[120]  Nonetheless, the company received a fairness opinion from a financial advisor that indicated the director’s offer was fair, based on valuation studies the advisor conducted.[121]

The board approved the merger, granted the bidding director a top-up option, and recommended the deal to the shareholders.[122]  The bidding director conducted a successful tender offer that did, however, leave him short of the 90% of the shares needed for a short-form merger.[123]  He then exercised his top-up option, acquired the shares he needed to reach 90% of the equity of the company, and performed a short-form merger—freezing out the minority nontendering shareholders by the end of the year.[124]

In the appraisal case brought by nontendering shareholders, the court did not rely on the auction price because it doubted the fairness of the auction and the effectiveness of the manner in which the auction was conducted.[125]  The court assumed that while “as a co-founder, insider, and director, [the bidding director] had access to internal projections and other inside information . . . it is unclear how the information regarding eMachines’ improving fortunes that was made available to [the outside bidders] compares to that available to [the inside director].”[126]  The court also noted that “[t]he quick termination of the bidding may have kept the price down and reduced the chances of another bidder entering the auction.”[127]  Thus, considering all factors available to it, the court came up with its own valuation of the company, a fair value of $1.64 per share.[128]

The difference between the tender-offer price of $1.06 and the price the court awarded, $1.64, an increase of about 55%, helps illustrate the potentially substantial agency costs that may be involved in a top-up option.  However, even though the bidding director lost the appraisal case and was ordered to pay 55% more than the offer price, he was forced to pay the higher price only to the former shareholders who exercised their appraisal right.[129]  Since only a small number of shareholders had exercised their appraisal rights, a mere 1,344,600 shares in total,[130] the bidding director had to pay less than $0.8 million extra,[131] which pales in comparison to his gain from the acquisition even when one only takes into account the company’s cash.[132]

In this case, the manager likely had inside information about the promising prospects of the company and thus may have benefited from the use of a top-up option that expedited the procedure, which was finalized before news about the positive change in the company’s forecast became public knowledge.  Not surprisingly, the other managers of the company supported their colleague, recommended the deal to the shareholders, and also granted a top-up option that facilitated the speedy completion of the acquisition.[133]

The appraisal route is the only remedy available to the dissenting shareholders after the short-form merger.[134]  It is possible, however, to try to challenge the actual grant of the top-up option by the board upon the announcement of the tri-step merger, which starts with the tender offer, proceeds with the exercise of the top-up option, and concludes with the short-form merger.  The grant of the top-up option is announced together with the imminent tender offer as part of one agreement between the bidder and the company.[135]  Challenging this agreement is not easy, and the main and clear beneficiary of such challenges seems to be the plaintiffs’ bar.  The following cases provide two examples of class actions that questioned the grant of a top-up option as part of a request for injunctive relief to prevent a tender offer from proceeding.  These proceedings help illustrate both the difficulty of challenging the grant of a top-up option under the current system and the potential agency costs associated with the top-up option.

In the case of the sale of ZymoGenetics, Inc. to Bristol-Myers Squibb Company, the plaintiffs asked the court for injunctive relief to stop the sale of ZymoGenetics.[136]  ZymoGenetics, a growing pharmaceutical company, was developing a few drugs that had a substantial market and a significant potential for success.[137]  The plaintiffs alleged that the directors of ZymoGenetics breached their fiduciary duties to the company’s shareholders by supporting the sale of the company for an allegedly unfair and low price in a process that included “unreasonable” devices.[138]  The complaint listed the top-up option as one of these devices and argued that its intent was to “circumvent the requirement of a shareholder vote.”[139]  The plaintiffs further alleged that the directors only agreed to the sale in order to further their own personal benefit.[140]  The complaint asserted that a few of the company’s directors had traded the interests of the shareholders for “hundreds of thousands of dollars in personal benefits.”[141]

Shortly after the filing of the complaint, the parties reached a settlement agreement.  The company and its directors continued to deny the plaintiffs’ claims; however, as part of the settlement the company agreed to provide the public shareholders additional information concerning the acquisition, including disclosing information of the transaction bonus that the CEO, who also served as a director, would receive upon the closing of the sale.[142]  The plaintiffs, on the other hand, continued to believe in the merit of their claims, yet plaintiffs’ counsel acknowledged the cost of continuing with the class action through trial and appeal, and the length of such proceedings, and determined that the settlement was in the best interests of the plaintiffs.[143]  As part of the settlement agreement the company also agreed to pay plaintiffs’ counsel $625,000 for attorneys’ fees and expenses incurred in association with the prosecution.[144]  Thus, the ZymoGenetics case shows that challenging the directors’ decision to grant a top-up option as part of a tender offer is not an easy task, but one that can be expensive for the company.

Another example of a futile attempt to receive injunctive relief in an acquisition involving a top-up option is the case of Cogent Inc., a developer of automated fingerprint identification systems, which was acquired by the conglomerate 3M Company.[145]  Here, too, the plaintiffs challenged the grant of the top-up option by the board not as part of appraisal proceedings prompted by the short-form merger, but rather beforehand as part of an attempt to stop the tender offer.[146]  The plaintiffs argued that the planned sale of the company was tainted because key employees, including the CEO who was one of its founders and served as president and chairman of the board, were personally interested in the merger, which promised them retention agreements.[147]

There was, however, another potential acquirer of the company who had offered more for the company.  The other potential acquirer was a competitor of Cogent.[148]  Yet, the court agreed with Cogent’s board that the deal with the competitor, which would require regulatory approval, involved a certain level of risk that justified preferring the deal with 3M despite the lower price.[149]  The court also considered the fact that Cogent’s chairman of the board had an exceptionally high equity interest in the company.[150]  This high equity interest in the company, the court reasoned, made it unlikely for the manager to favor a lower priced deal just because the bidder promises him a relatively insignificant retention bonus.[151]  Indeed, from a purely economic perspective, the increase in the purchase price would have more than covered the offered bonus in this case.

However, the likelihood that a manager would remain in charge of the operations of a company following a merger with a competitor seems less probable than the likelihood that his services would be needed if the company merged into an acquirer whose operations do not compete with the target.  The difference in the expertise of the employees of the acquirer, 3M, and the target, Cogent, two companies that were not competitors and did not operate in the same market, made retention of the target’s employees more likely.

Many founders value retention and remaining in control of the company not merely because of the continued pecuniary benefits they receive from the company, but also because controlling the company has an additional reputational and psychological value associated with the status of managing the company.  This added value of continuing to manage the company is not easily quantifiable.  For example, it was recently reported that Mark Zuckerberg, the founder and CEO of Facebook Inc., had declined an acquisition offer made by Microsoft, not because the offered price was too low, but merely because Mr. Zuckerberg was reluctant to relinquish control of Facebook.[152]  Thus, in spite of the large equity interest that the manager of Cogent had in the sale of the company, he may well have had an additional interest in the identity of the acquirer and his possible future relationship with the company that may have also influenced his decision to support the sale to 3M.[153]

In refusing to grant a preliminary injunction, the court in Cogent explained that this remedy is issued only when the plaintiff can clearly show an “imminent irreparable harm.”[154]  The court was not convinced that this was a case of irreparable harm, relying in part on the availability of the appraisal remedy: “Fully informed stockholders may voluntarily choose not to tender their shares and instead seek appraisal under DGCL § 262.”[155]

Following the Delaware Chancery Court’s denial of the request for a preliminary injunction in the Cogent case, the impression among practitioners has been that “the use of top-up options is likely to present little litigation risk.”[156]  To be sure, this result is reassuring to both boards of targets who wish to support the friendly bidder and the bidder herself.[157]

In the absence of a top-up option, a bidder who wishes to acquire the entire target company and freeze out all of the shareholders, but has not succeeded in owning at least 90% of the shares following the tender offer, can still proceed with her acquisition plan.  After acquiring the majority of the shares in the tender offer, the bidder can buy out the minority shareholders who did not wish to participate in the tender offer in a subsequent merger.  Owning less than 90% of the shares, however, forces the acquirer to conduct a statutory long form merger rather than a short-form merger.  Owning the majority of the shares allows the acquirer to approve a merger.[158]  Yet, owning the majority of the shares also transforms the acquirer into a controlling shareholder of the target, and thus subjects the subsequent merger to the enhanced and stringent fiduciary duty of entire fairness.[159]

A top-up option, on the other hand, converts the acquirer to a 90% shareholder and thus permits the use of a short-form merger.  This transformation is critical, since it subjects the freeze-out merger only to the lax requirement[160] of a possible appraisal procedure.  Thus, the top-up option allows the bidder to avoid entire-fairness review while freezing out the opposing shareholders, even without gaining the support of the holders of 90% of the target’s shares.

Adding a top-up option enables the holder of the majority of the shares to avoid fairness review in a freeze out of the minority even without reaching the threshold of 90% of the company’s equity.  Ignoring the will of nontendering shareholders who together own only a trivial number of shares may, at times, be efficient and serve the interests of all the shareholders, including the nontendering ones.  For example, it may be that a collective action problem is responsible for a few of the nontendered shares: some retail investors who did not tender may have done so only because they had not received the tender request or understood that they were asked to respond to the request.  However, while this may explain the behavior of a few shareholders, the closer we get to 50% nontendered shares the less likely it is that we face a collective action problem, but rather a different problem.  Forcing the holders of more than 10% of the equity of the target out with only the lenient appraisal protection may not serve the collective good.  In fact, as shown before, it may allow the bidder to pay the shareholders a lower price.[161]

Acquirers often prefer to use a tender offer followed by a short-form merger rather than a regular long-form merger.  One of the main reasons why acquirers prefer the two-step acquisition of a tender offer and a subsequent short-form merger is that it takes less time to complete.[162]  However, this expeditiousness may hurt the target’s shareholders, who are left with less time to consider the transaction.  Of even more concern is the fact that less time is left for competitors to enter the scene and compete with the bidder for the target.[163]

Not surprisingly, the use of a top-up option in tender offer acquisitions has dramatically increased since the middle of the last decade.[164]  The ubiquity of the top-up option highlights the importance of the power to issue stock and also helps camouflage managerial attempts to abuse the power to issue stock through the grant of the option because it has become the custom.

3. The White Squire

Similar to the poison pill and the top-up option, a white squire is a technique that uses stock issuances to make sure the managers’ wishes prevail despite shareholder opposition.[165]  Managers use a white squire to prevent a hostile bid the shareholders may favor.  Wishing to maintain their position with the corporation, the managers sell a block of shares to a friendly investor who subsequently opposes the hostile takeover and allows the managers to keep their jobs.[166]  Managers’ entrenchment motives explain the use of a white squire in the shadow of a hostile takeover where blocking the change of control does not seem to coincide with the best interests of the shareholders.[167]

For example, the management of Walt Disney Productions used its power to issue stock, which enabled it to recruit a white squire as part of its resistance techniques aimed at fending off a hostile bidder.[168]  In 1984, Disney faced the threat of a hostile bid for the company orchestrated by the corporate raider Saul Steinberg.  Steinberg initiated the proposed takeover by acquiring a large toehold—an equity stake in Disney.[169]  The management of Disney enlisted a friendly acquirer who purchased about 10% of Disney’s shares in exchange for a land development firm that Disney bought.[170]  The new block of shares issued to the friendly white squire diluted the hostile bidder and helped block the bidder’s attempt to take over Disney.[171]

It should be noted that straight vote buying, that is, managers’ use of the company’s resources to control the outcome of a shareholder vote, is specifically limited.  Shareholder voting agreements are generally permitted.[172]  However, in order to protect the shareholders from fraudulent behavior by management, the transfer of stock voting rights to management is prohibited if “the object or purpose is to defraud or in some way disenfranchise the other stockholders.”[173]  Such a transfer of voting rights is “a voidable transaction subject to a test for intrinsic fairness.”[174]  Instead of directly buying the vote, the managers create additional votes through their power to issue stock and distribute those newly created votes, along with the new shares, selectively.  Thus, vote-buying effectively can take a less direct form, such as the use of a white squire or a top-up option, which is much more difficult to challenge.

D.            Restrictions on the Power to Issue Shares

The previous Subpart showed that the power to issue stock can be exploited to the detriment of the shareholders.  The power to issue stock serves as a significant building block for power tools in the managers’ arsenal that can be used to circumvent the will of the shareholders.  Understanding the contours of the power to issue stock can be crucial in assessing the effectiveness of the firm’s corporate governance.  Thus, this Subpart examines the restrictions on the managerial power to issue stock.

1. Quantitative Restrictions

As seen above, in Delaware the difference between the size of the authorized capital—predetermined in the company’s certificate of incorporation—and the number of already issued shares, serves as an upper limit on how many shares management can issue without the shareholders’ approval.  In order to raise this ceiling, the certificate of incorporation of the company has to be amended to incorporate the increased number of authorized shares.  Such amendment can only be done with shareholder approval.  Provided there is a sufficient amount of authorized-and-unissued shares, however, Delaware corporate law does not restrict management’s ability to issue shares.

There is no limit in Delaware on the size of the authorized capital that may be set in the certificate of incorporation.[175]  A large capital may increase the fees that a corporation has to pay the Delaware Secretary of State because the fees are calculated based on the value of the corporation’s capital.[176]  The annual franchise tax, however, is capped and the maximum amount a Delaware corporation may be required to pay is $180,000 per year, a relatively insignificant expense for large public corporations.[177]

Other systems impose different quantitative restrictions on the power to issue stock without shareholder approval.  For example, under the German Stock Corporation Act the total amount of authorized shares may be increased by the shareholders to allow management to issue new shares.[178]  However, the total amount of authorized-but-unissued shares is limited to a maximum amount that should not exceed half the amount of the issued shares at the time of authorization by the shareholders.[179]

The listing requirements of stock exchanges provide another example of linking the higher limit of the amount of shares management can issue without asking for a new shareholder approval to the amount of issued shares.  Both the New York Stock Exchange and NASDAQ listing rules cap the maximum number of shares that the managers can issue without going to the shareholders at 20% of the number of issued shares.[180]  The experience with the listing rules’ restrictions on the power to issue stock indicates that they may have a real effect on the corporate governance of companies.

For example, NASDAQ reported attempts by managers to coerce a favorable shareholder vote on issuances of shares through entering into agreements that provide that the company is penalized and the bidder rewarded if shareholders deny approval of additional issuances.[181]  Such coercive transactions can stipulate a different price per share depending on the outcome of the shareholder vote: If the shareholders do not approve the transaction, then the investor will buy shares only up to the 20% cap in accordance with the listing rules, but will pay a much lower price per share than the price the investor would pay if the shareholders approve the issuance of more than 20% of the issued shares.  NASDAQ has recognized such behavior as coercive and strictly enforces the 20% cap rule, rejecting any attempts to influence the shareholder vote and circumvent the 20% cap rule.[182]

On the other hand, it may seem that the restrictions imposed by the listing rules fall short of the desired outcome in situations where the potential penalty for violating these restrictions, the delisting of the company, no longer poses a real threat to the company.  For example, where management considers issuing a top-up option to a bidder that will result in the issuance of more than 20% of the company’s shares without shareholder approval, it does not need to consider the outcome of delisting the company.  Following the exercise of the top-up option and the subsequent short-form merger with the bidder, the company will no longer exist as a separate legal entity; thus, the threat of delisting becomes irrelevant.  Not surprisingly, then, a top-up option agreement commonly states that lack of compliance with the stock exchange listing requirements does not release the company from its obligation to issue shares pursuant to the top-up option.[183]

2. Class Vote Restriction

A dual-class capital structure can be used in an attempt to circumvent the quantitative restrictions on the power to issue stock.  Section 151(e) of the Delaware Code allows for the issuance of convertible shares.[184]  A convertible share may be converted into a share of another class.  For example, a convertible preferred share can be converted into a common share.  Furthermore, the Delaware law permits the board of directors to set an exchange rate greater than one.[185]  For example, one convertible preferred share can be converted into ten common shares.  There is no statutory limit to the size of the conversion rate used for determining into how many common shares one convertible preferred share can be converted.  Issuing preferred shares convertible into common stock at more than a 1:1 ratio can partially circumvent the limitation on the amount of shares that can be issued, which the maximum number of authorized shares of the company imposes.

A sufficient amount of authorized-but-unissued common stock, however, is required for the conversion of the preferred stock into common stock.  Indeed, it is common for venture capital funds, which invest through convertible preferred stock, to require that the company undertake to reserve common stock for the future conversion of the preferred stock into common stock and to keep a sufficient amount of unissued common stock for the conversion.[186]  Yet, until the actual conversion takes place, the preferred stockholder can have the right to vote along with the common stockholders on an as converted basis, as if the preferred shares were converted into common shares, assigning more voting rights per one single preferred share than per one common share.

The Design Within Reach, Inc. example exemplifies the use of convertible preferred shares due to lack of authorized but unissued common stock.[187]  In this case there were not enough authorized shares of common stock that could have been issued to Glenhill in exchange for its investment of $15 million in the company.[188]  Instead, the company issued preferred shares convertible into common stock so that the investor owned about 91% of the company in a combination of common stock and convertible preferred stock, without a shareholder vote approving the stock issuance or any other part of the transaction.[189]

The ability of the augmented voting rights of the preferred shares to circumvent the quantitative restrictions on the power to issue stock is, however, also limited.  If a class vote is required, a favorable vote by a majority of each class of shares separately is needed, and thus issuing preferred stock is not a good substitute for common stock.  Approval of a short-form merger under Delaware law requires a class vote.[190]  Under Delaware law a short-form merger requires owning at least 90% of each class of the voting shares and not just 90% of the aggregated rights to vote as one group.[191]  As discussed above, short-form merger is the ultimate step in the top-up option scheme.[192]  Thus, a top-up option requires the issuance of a substantial number of common shares and cannot rely on a dual-class capital structure.[193]

Unlike the top-up option, the poison pill can, in theory, rely on the issuance of only blank-check preferred stock[194] if the certificate authorized the managers to issue such class of preferred stock that is assigned higher voting rights and distribution rights than the common stock.  It is, however, common practice to have a poison pill that uses preferred stock convertible into common stock and thus still requires a large amount of common shares for the conversion.  In addition, poison pills often include a provision that explicitly allows the company to distribute cash, assets, and other securities instead of common stock, if the company does not have sufficient common stock when the poison pill is triggered.[195]  The poison pill is intended to deter a hostile takeover by credibly threatening the dilution of the value of the hostile bidder and not merely its voting rights.  Thus, the technique of replacing share distribution with asset distribution, in this case, can effectively circumvent a limit requirement on the number of shares management can issue without going back to the shareholders.  Yet, this technique will not suffice where the desired stock distribution is mainly aimed at increasing the voting rights of the intended recipients of the shares, as in the case of a top-up option where the bidder still needs to own 90% of each class of shares to be able to perform a short-form merger.

3. Qualitative Restriction

The previous Subpart illustrated the deficiencies of challenging management’s use of the power to issue stock in court.  It is very difficult to prove that the purpose of a specific stock issuance lacks good faith and breaches the fiduciary duties of the managers.  In addition, the previous Subpart discussed the shortcomings of the remedy of appraisal, which may be the only available remedy following the issuance of the shares.[196]

Attempts to limit managers’ general ability to issue stock only to ordinary, nonorganic purposes, such as financing ordinary business operations of the company, have failed.  In Moran v. Household International, the Delaware Supreme Court[197] rejected an interpretation of the Delaware statute that limits managers’ power to issue securities only for corporate finance related purposes.[198]  The court has explicitly allowed managers to use their power for nonfinance related purposes such as corporate control related issuances.[199]  In a recent case, following the Delaware Supreme Court in Moran, the Delaware Chancery Court upheld a record long use of a poison pill[200] that prevented a hostile takeover.[201]

4. Preemptive Rights Restriction

Preemption rights allow the shareholders to participate pro rata in any distribution of shares by the company.[202]  The following example illustrates how preemptive rights work.  A company has issued 100 shares and plans to issue another 10 new shares.  Assuming a shareholder has preemptive rights and currently holds 10% of the company, she is entitled to purchase one newly issued share, which represents 10% of the total amount of new shares being issued by the company.  Should the shareholder choose to exercise her preemptive right and purchase the new share, she will then own a total of 11 shares out of the 110 shares of the company, maintaining her 10% holding in the company.

If the shareholders exercise their preemptive rights, they will maintain their percentage holding in the company and prevent dilution by the issuance of new shares.  To the extent that the shareholders have preemptive rights and exercise these rights fully each time the company issues new shares, management’s ability to issue shares cannot circumvent the shareholders’ will, rendering corporate mechanisms such as a poison pill and a top-up option futile.

Preemptive rights are no longer mandatory in the United States.[203]  Other jurisdictions, on the other hand, still treat preemptive rights as a basic mandatory right of the shareholders and enforce stringent restrictions on the ability to waive these rights.  For example, under the German Stock Corporation Act preemptive rights are mandatory and can be waived only if the company issues no more than 10% of the issued capital and provided that at least 75% of the shareholders’ votes approve the waiver.[204]

However, preemptive rights give only the right to participate in future issuances of shares, but the shareholders’ ability to participate in the issuance of shares may in itself be limited.  Participation in a distribution of shares requires paying for the newly issued shares.  Liquidity constraints, as well as collective action problems, can prevent shareholders from exercising preemptive rights.  A shareholder may not want or be able to invest more in the company and may prefer, for example, to diversify her investment and use any available funds to pursue a different business opportunity.  This weakness of preemptive rights may explain why venture capital investors, who customarily require preemptive rights as a condition for their investment in private firms, also negotiate for the right to acquire more shares in new issuances if other existing shareholders fail to exercise their preemptive rights and purchase their entire pro rata share.[205]

II.  The Excess Ratio

After reviewing the key aspects of management’s power to issue stock and analyzing possible implications of this power, I now turn to study the magnitude of the managers’ power to issue stock empirically.  As seen above, one of the major limitations on this power is the size of the authorized capital of the corporation, which provides a ceiling for the total number of shares that can be issued without shareholder approval.[206]  The relative size of the number of authorized shares versus the number of shares already issued determines the extent of management’s power to issue shares.  Thus, the ratio of the authorized shares not outstanding to the already-issued-and-outstanding shares, what I shall call the “excess ratio,” is an indicator of the magnitude of the managers’ power to issue stock.

For example, an excess ratio of one signifies that there are enough authorized-but-not-outstanding shares to double the number of shares already issued and outstanding.  The stock exchanges’ requirement of shareholder approval for an increase of more than 20% of the issued share is equivalent to a 0.2 excess ratio,[207] and the German limit of 50% can be expressed as a 0.5 excess ratio.[208]

A study of initial public offerings of nonfinancial companies[209] incorporated in Delaware reveals that companies choose to go public with a significantly high excess ratio.  I use the data in prospectuses of nonfinancial Delaware companies, which were filed with the Securities and Exchange Commission, to calculate the excess ratios of the companies at the time of the initial public offering.  In 2009, the average excess ratio of the companies in my sample was 5.79 and the median ratio was 3.75.  This high excess ratio allows the management of the firms to more than quadruple the number of issued shares without asking the shareholders for their approval to issue more stock.[210]  Similar results were obtained when the excess ratio was measured for companies that went public in 2008.  The excess ratio, at the time of the initial public offering, of companies that went public in 2003 was also checked since the use of the top-up option, which requires a high excess ratio, has increased since 2004.[211]  The average ratio of firms that went public in 2003 was also significantly high and only slightly lower than in more recent years.  The study found a substantial deviation in the excess ratio: some companies choose to go public with an exceptionally high ratio and the highest ratio in the sample was 25.  Other companies choose to have a relatively low ratio—the lowest in the sample was 0.34.  The following table summarizes these findings.

 

Table 3: Excess Ratios

 

Year

Mean Excess Ratio

Median Excess Ratio

Standard Deviation

Sample Size

2009 5.79 3.75 5.13 28
2008 4.74 3.17 5.87 16
2003 4.55 3.26 3.08 37

 

The study also looked at venture-backed firms separately.  On the one hand, venture capitalists customarily restrict the managers’ ability to issue shares at the private stage of the company.[212]  This indicates that these sophisticated investors are aware of the importance of the managers’ power to issue stock.  On the other hand, venture capitalists may be inclined to enable management to issue a top-up option because of the typical, relatively short-run focus of these investors.[213]  The excess ratio of the venture-backed firms was slightly higher than that of nonventure-backed firms that went public in the same year.  However, the study did not find a statistically significant difference between the excess ratio of the two sets of firms, suggesting that the use of a high excess ratio is not unique to venture-backed firms.

The study found that the use of a high ratio at the time of an initial public offering is prevalent, yet there was no statistical indication that the size of the firm is related to the size of the ratio.[214]  In the years following the public offering, the excess ratio of the firms declined if management issued additional shares.  However, the average excess ratio of venture backed firms that went public in 2004 was notably high 5 years following the public offering, and was on average 3.15.  This finding may suggest that the high ratio is not used for regular stock issuances, either because they are not required or because managers are cautious about weakening their power to dilute the shareholders in the future by issuing in the present.

In addition, the study checked for a relation between the size of the excess ratio at the time of the initial public offering and the likelihood of a future acquisition.  The study looked at the 83 venture-backed companies that went public in 2004.  Out of these companies, 29 were acquired by the end of 2010.  A check for a relation between the excess ratio and the likelihood of future acquisitions did not find a statistically significant correlation between the two.  It should be noted, however, that even though a high excess ratio may have an influence on whether the company is acquired or stays independent, a high excess ratio helps management in both opposing directions.  On the one hand, a high ratio may help management sell the company through the use of a top-up option, and on the other hand, the high ratio may help management prevent a sale through the use of a poison pill or a white squire.

The following table summarizes the mean and median excess ratio of 264 venture-backed Delaware firms that went public in the years 2004–2009.

 

Table 4: Averages of Mean and Median Excess Ratios

 

Excess Ratio

2004

2005

2006

2007

2008

2009

All

Mean

6.16

4.61

4.69

4.85

7.31

3.16

5.21

Median

3.82

3.48

3.58

3.99

5.08

3.50

3.69

 

Conclusion

This Article studied the important managerial power to issue stock and shows that shareholders are vulnerable to managers exploiting this power to promote their own self-interest.  On the one hand, the power to issue stock can be used to create entrenchment mechanisms that prevent a sale of the company, and on the other hand, it can help form mechanisms that promote the sale of the company despite significant shareholder opposition.

Even though there are limitations on the managers’ power to issue stock, this Article shows that most of these limitations do not effectively restrict this power and that managers can still take advantage of it to advance their own interests.  Furthermore, the only restriction that can effectively prevent the managers from issuing substantial amounts of shares without receiving the shareholders’ approval—the ceiling set by the number of authorized shares—can distort managerial behavior.  This limit on the power to issue stock may influence the managers to refrain from issuing stock for ordinary business purposes, such as equity financing and performance based compensation, in order to retain their power.

A study of a proxy for the magnitude of the power to issue stock, as is measured by the excess ratio, revealed that companies tend to go public with a significantly high ratio that allows management to more than quadruple the amount of issued shares without shareholder approval.  This incidence of a high ratio, which indicates a significant power in managers’ hands, can be desirable to the extent that it allows the managers to issue stock without worrying about diminishing their power.  On the other hand, mechanisms such as a top-up option require the issuance of such a substantial amount of new shares that managers may nonetheless remain cautious about share issuances despite a high excess ratio.

Further study of the excess ratio may enhance our understanding of corporate governance and of managerial decision-making processes.  Such a study may look at a possible relation between personal characteristics of management and the size of the ratio.  In addition, a study of a possible correlation between the size of the excess ratio and the existence of entrenchment mechanisms may expose interesting patterns, since the excess ratio can serve as an alternative or as a complementary tool.  Similarly, a study of the correlation between the excess ratio and the existence of tools aimed at monitoring management, such as independent directors, can increase our understanding of corporate governance.

 


* Assistant Professor, University of Texas School of Law.  I am indebted to Jesse Fried for invaluable discussions and comments.  I am grateful for the help, insight, support, and encouragement of Willy Forbath.  I would also like to thank Hans Baade, Brian Broughman, Jens Dammann, Ron Fink, George Geis, Sarah Lawsky, Dick Markovits, Karl Okamoto, Gordon Smith, Matt Spitzer, Deborah Weiss, Sean Williams, and participants in the Law & Entrepreneurship Conference at LSA for very helpful discussions, comments, and suggestions.  Jennifer Georg, Shane Johnson, Kris Teng, and the editors of the Wake Forest Law Review provided valuable editorial assistance.

Comments are welcome and can be sent to me at [email protected].

[1]. Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 161 (2010).  For limitations of this right, see infra Part I.D.  In addition, specific contractual requirements may also require a shareholder approval on specific share issuances.

[2]. This is because the total value of the company increases by the value of the added consideration that the company receives for the newly issued shares.

[3]. Poison Pill, Fin. Times Lexicon, http://lexicon.ft.com/Term?term=poison
-pill (last visited Sept. 15, 2011).

[4]. See, e.g., Lucian Arye Bebchuk et al., The Powerful Antitakeover Force of Staggered Boards: Theory, Evidence and Policy, 54 Stan. L. Rev. 887, 904–05 (2002) (describing the poison pill).  See id. at 905 n.59 for a discussion of the flip-in pill, which is the more common and potent version of the pill and infra Part I.B, discussing this version of the poison pill.

[5]. Bebchuk et al., supra note 4, at 903–04.

[6]. See, e.g., John Letzing, Yahoo Vulnerable if Microsoft Goes ‘Hostile, MarketWatch (Feb. 11, 2008, 6:34 PM), http://www.marketwatch.com/story
/story/print?guid=CB075A77-BD12-417C-B880-9063B4E0DEC4 (quoting Shirley Westcott of Proxy Governance) (“Yahoo has a ‘poison pill,’ and that pretty much blocks the consummation of any kind of tender offer.”).

[7]. Id.

[8]. See, e.g., Andrei Shleifer & Robert W. Vishny, Management Entrenchment: The Case of Manager-Specific Investments, 25 J. Fin. Econ. 123, 137 (1989).

[9]. For a description and examples of the use of a white squire, see infra Part I.C.3.

[10]. See generally, e.g., Mira Ganor, Why Do Managers Dismantle Staggered Boards?, 33 Del. J. Corp. L. 149 (2008) [hereinafter Ganor, Why Do Managers Dismantle Staggered Boards?]; Mira Ganor, Salvaged Directors or Perpetual Thrones?, 5 Va. L. & Bus. Rev. 267 (2010) [hereinafter Ganor, Salvaged Directors or Perpetual Thrones?] (suggesting managers at times prefer to sell the company to advance their own interests).

[11]. See Jim Mallea, M&A Year End Review, FactSet Mergers (Jan. 23, 2009), https://www.factsetmergers.com/marequest?an=dt.getPage&st=1&pg
=/pub/rs_20090122.html&rnd=101994 (“In 2004, 35% of agreed tender offers included a top-up option. . . . In 2008, the inclusion of a top-up option had become standard as 100% of all agreed tender offers included one.”).

[12]. Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 253 (2010).

[13]. For a description of the antitakeover mechanism known as a white squire as well as for an example of the use of a white squire to thwart a hostile takeover, see infra Part I.C.3.

[14]. See generally Ganor, Why Do Managers Dismantle Staggered Boards?, supra note 10; Ganor, Salvaged Directors or Perpetual Thrones?, supra note 10.

[15]. Several commentators support the use of a poison pill by arguing that the pill may help directors negotiate and reach a better outcome for the shareholders.  See generally, e.g., Stephen Bainbridge, Director Primacy and Shareholder Disempowerment, 119 Harv. L. Rev. 1735 (2006); Martin Lipton & William Savitt, The Many Myths of Lucian Bebchuk, 93 Va. L. Rev. 733 (2007); see also Ganor, Salvaged Directors or Perpetual Thrones?, supra note 10 (acknowledging that under certain circumstances, granting perpetual thrones can be efficient).

[16]. For example, a poison pill can be efficient where managers have nonpublic information that the company’s prospects are much better than the market thinks and disclosing this information prematurely will hurt the company.  Without this information being publicly available, a hostile bidder is likely to convince the shareholders to sell the company at a fraction of its true value.

[17]. See infra Part II.D (describing the limitations of the power to issue stock).

[18]. See Richard S. Markovits, Monopoly and the Allocative Inefficiency of First-Best-Allocatively-Efficient Tort Law in Our Worse-Than-Second-Best World: The Whys and Some Therefores, 46 Case W. Res. L. Rev. 313, 329–30 (1996) (discussing the general theory of Second Best, the deficiency of an isolated allocative-efficiency analysis without a study of the aggregate effects, and the applications of this theory to the law).

[19]. Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 102 (2010).

[20]. Id.

[21]. For an example of a Maryland corporation that went public with a charter provision that allows its board of directors to issue an unlimited number of shares without shareholder approval, see Under Armour, Inc., Prospectus 85 (Nov. 17, 2005), available at http://files.shareholder.com/downloads/UARM
/494263049x0x60177/D03013EC‑AECD‑4604‑8E42‑C19ABD3F9CF2/S‑111.17.05.pdf (“[Our charter] permits our board to amend the charter without stockholder approval to increase or decrease the aggregate number of shares of stock or the number of shares of stock of any class or series that we have authority to issue and to classify or reclassify unissued shares of stock.”).

[22]. Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 161 (2010).

[23]. Id. § 102(a)(4).

[24]. Cf. NYSE, Listed Company Manual § 312.03(c) (2002), http://nysemanual.nyse.com; NASDAQ, Corporate Governance Requirements, http://www.nasdaq.com/about/nasdaq_listing_req_fees.pdf (stating that NASDAQ Rule 5635 requires shareholder approval for issuance of common stock equal to or greater than twenty percent of preissued shares subject to certain exceptions, such as a public offering).

[25]. See infra Part I.D.4 (discussing preemptive rights).

[26]. There is evidence that managers can also be influenced by tools less conventional than regular voting on shareholder resolutions, such as vote-withholding techniques and voting on nonbinding, precatory resolutions.  These tools also use the voting power assigned to the shares to pressure the managers to conform to the will of the shareholders.  See generally Ganor, Why do Managers Dismantle Staggered Boards?, supra note 10.

[27]. See generally Lucian Arye Bebchuk, The Case for Increasing Shareholder Power, 118 Harv. L. Rev. 833 (2005).

[28]. See, e.g., Bainbridge, supra note 15; Lipton & Savitt, supra note 15.

[29]. See generally Henry T.C. Hu & Bernard Black, The New Vote Buying: Empty Voting and Hidden (Morphable) Ownership, 79 S. Cal. L. Rev. 811 (2006).

[30]. See, e.g., Andrew J. Opiola, Should Shares Issued Directly From a Corporation Constitute a Control Share Acquisition?, 1 J. Bus. & Tech. L. 207, 226 (2006).

[31]. See id.

[32]. See id.

[33]. See id.

[34]. Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 161 (2010).

[35]. Id.

[36]. See id. § 102(a)(4).

[37]. See id. (requiring certificates of incorporation to include the number of authorized shares); id. § 242(b)(2) (requiring the approval of the affected class of shareholders for any amendment that changes the number of authorized shares of the class).  Maryland is an exception to this rule, for it does not require a shareholder vote to increase the number of authorized shares.  See supra note 21 and accompanying text.

[38]. Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 161 (2010).

[39]. See id.

[40]. See Matteo Arena & Stephen P. Ferris, When Managers Bypass Shareholder Approval of Board Appointments, 13 J. Corp. Fin. 4, § 3.1 (2007).

[41]. Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 161 (2010).

[42]. Absent transaction costs, taxes, and inefficient markets, the choice between debt and equity should not affect the value of the firm.  See generally Franco Modigliani & Merton H. Miller, The Cost of Capital, Corporation Finance and the Theory of Investment, 48 Am. Econ. Rev. 261 (1958).  However, since companies operate in inefficient markets with transaction costs and taxes, the capital structure of the firm factors into the value of the firm.

[43]. Cash and equity compensation are not equivalent even when they have equal values.  The grant of cash rather than equity has different effects on the company and on the recipient.  For one, equity-based compensation is generally believed to align the interests of the employees with those of the company.  See infra note 64 and accompanying text.

[44]. It should be noted that quorum and majority requirements are calculated based on the number of outstanding shares and that the company is not allowed to vote or use treasury shares to satisfy the quorum requirement.  See Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 160(c) (2010).

[45]. See id. § 160(a).

[46]. For an analysis of potential costs and benefits of share repurchases on managerial cash-hoarding practice, see Jesse M. Fried, Informed Trading and False Signaling with Open Market Repurchases, 93 Cal. L. Rev. 1323, 1371 (2005) (“To the extent that the prospect of future bargain repurchase opportunities lead [sic] to cash hoarding, managers’ ability to engage in such repurchases does not mitigate the problem of free cash retention.”).

[47]. See, e.g., id. at 1326 (“[T]he use of share repurchases to distribute cash has since grown substantially in the United States, increasing from $6.6 billion in 1980 to almost $200 billion in 2000.”); Douglas J. Skinner, The Evolving Relation Between Earnings, Dividends, and Stock Repurchases, 87 J. Fin. Econ. 582, 585 (2008) (stating that newer firms with no history of paying dividends (like Cisco and Dell) tend to rely exclusively on stock repurchases and are unlikely to initiate dividends, helping to explain the declining propensity to pay dividends; since 1980, these firms display an increasing tendency to use repurchases rather than dividends; repurchases now represent about half of total payouts).

[48]. See Fried, supra note 46, at 1327–28.

[49]. Id.

[50]. Id.

[51]. Id. at 1327–29.

[52]. Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 152 (2010) (“The board of directors may authorize capital stock to be issued for consideration consisting of cash, any tangible or intangible property or any benefit to the corporation, or any combination thereof.”).

[53]. Id. (“In the absence of actual fraud in the transaction, the judgment of the directors as to the value of such consideration shall be conclusive.”).  Similar rules govern the issuance of options to purchase shares.  Id. § 157; see also Zupnick v. Goizueta, 698 A.2d 384, 387 (Del. Ch. 1997) (“[S]o long as there is any consideration for the issuance of shares or options, the sufficiency of the consideration fixed by the directors cannot be challenged in the absence of actual fraud.  Only where it is claimed that the issuance of shares or options was entirely without consideration will § 157 not operate as ‘a legal barrier to any claim for relief as to an illegal gift or waste of corporate assets in the issuance of stock options.’” (quoting Michelson v. Duncan, 407 A.2d 211, 224 (Del. 1979))).

[54]. Blades v. Wisehart, No. 5317-VCS, 2010 Del. Ch. LEXIS 227, at *28–29 (Del Ch. Nov. 17, 2010) (“[I]n order to effect a forward or reverse stock split, the corporation must follow the prescribed corporate formalities to amend its certificate of incorporation in such a manner that ‘splits’ the outstanding shares in accordance with the corporation’s intentions.”).  Cf. Jesse M. Fried, Firms Gone Dark, 76 U. Chi. L. Rev. 135, 142 (2009) (“Some state corporate laws may permit a reverse stock split without shareholder approval in certain circumstances.”); Minn. Stat. Ann. § 302A.137(a) (West 2010).

[55]. See Definitions, US Legal, http://definitions.uslegal.com/d/debt
-financing (last visited Sept. 15, 2011).

[56]. See Massimo G. Colombo & Luca Grilli, Funding Gaps? Access to Bank Loans By High-Tech Start-Ups, 29 Small Bus. Econ. 25, 28 (2006).

[57]. To be sure, there may be exceptions to this limitation on raising debt.  For example, a very reputable entrepreneur who founds a new startup after prior proven success may not face much difficulty raising any type of financing for the new start-up, including debt.  Financial institutions may choose to assume the risk and waive the collateral requirement, but they are likely to ask for individual guaranties in most situations.

[58]. See supra note 42 and accompanying text.

[59]. The Modigliani-Miller theorem shows that the method of finance chosen does not affect the value of the firm as long as the markets are efficient and there are no transaction costs and no taxes.  However, once taxes, transaction costs, and inefficient markets are introduced, the capital structure of the corporation can have a notable effect on the value of the firm.  See Modigliani & Miller, supra note 42.

[60]. See, e.g., Brian Cheffins & John Armour, The Eclipse of Private Equity, 33 Del. J. Corp. L. 1, 13 (2008) (“Debt covenants typically . . . oblig[e] executives to operate the company within tight budgetary and operational constraints.”).

[61]. See Alon Chaver & Jesse M. Fried, Managers’ Fiduciary Duty Upon the Firm’s Insolvency: Accounting for Performance Creditors, 55 Vand. L. Rev. 1813, 1823 (2002) (“[M]anagers required to maximize creditor value when the firm is insolvent might forgo risky opportunities that increase total value because they make creditors worse off.  This problem, of course, is the inevitable result of an approach that seeks to maximize creditor value without regard to the effect on shareholder value. . . . The intuition behind this . . . is that creditors bear most of the downside if the firm does poorly but do not enjoy much of the upside if the firm does very well.”).

[62]. See Jesse M. Fried & Mira Ganor, Agency Costs of Venture Capitalist Control in Startups, 81 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 967, 976 (2006).

[63]. See id. at 1010.

[64]. See, e.g., id. (“[E]quity compensation aligns the interests of employees with those of shareholders.”).  Equity compensation can also be used as a substitute for cash compensation when the company cannot compete for talent on the basis of salaries, as is frequently the case with startups.  See id. (“Equity compensation allows liquidity-constrained firms, which are unable to pay competitive salaries and cash bonuses, to compete in the labor market for talented employees.”); see also Ganor, Why Do Managers Dismantle Staggered Boards?, supra note 10, at 162 (studying the connection between CEO equity holdings and the decision to de-stagger the board, based on the hypothesis that “[t]he CEO’s equity holdings help to create an interest in the increase of the company’s value, or at least in the stock price (the perceived market value of the company)”).

[65]. See, e.g., Lucian Arye Bebchuk et al., Managerial Power and Rent Extraction in the Design of Executive Compensation, 69 U. Chi. L. Rev. 751, 763, 783–86 (2002) (criticizing prevailing equity compensation practices for providing suboptimal incentives); Hu & Black, supra note 29, at 831–32 (analyzing managers’ custom of hedging their personal exposure by purchasing financial instruments such as zero-cost collar); Eli Ofek & David Yermack, Taking Stock: Equity-Based Compensation and the Evolution of Managerial Ownership, 55 J. Fin. 1367, 1367–68 (2000) (reporting that managers can hedge the risk of equity-based compensation, yet companies justify the use of equity incentive compensation by arguing that it helps reduce agency problems).

[66]. See, e.g., Lucian A. Bebchuk & Jesse M. Fried, Paying for Long-Term Performance, 158 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1915, 1919–20 (2010) (suggesting limitations on equity-based compensation that will optimally tie managerial pay to long-term performance).

[67]. To be sure, while scaling down the core operations of the company, managers may prefer to use scarce resources on empire building which includes sizable acquisitions of other businesses for the purpose of increasing the managers’ power and increasing the size of the company.  This makes it more difficult to take over the company and helps to entrench the managers.

[68]. Guhan Subramanian, Bargaining in the Shadow of PeopleSoft’s (Defective) Poison Pill, 12 Harv. Negot. L. Rev. 41, 42–43 (2007) (“It is widely believed that a poison pill, even a plain vanilla pill, is a ‘show-stopper’ against a hostile bidder because it severely dilutes an acquirer’s stake if triggered.”); see also Jonathan R. Macey, The Legality and Utility of the Shareholder Rights Bylaw, 26 Hofstra L. Rev. 835, 837 (1998) (“Target firms can now keep their poison pills in place and ‘just say no’ to would-be acquirers, regardless of the market premiums these acquirers are willing to pay to shareholders.”).

[69]. See Macey, supra note 68, at 839.

[70]. See id.

[71]. 10 million ÷ 190 million = 5.26%

[72]. 5.26% × $1,450 million = $76.3 million

[73]. See Subramanian, supra note 68, at 44 (studying the poison pills of “U.S. publicly-traded software companies with market capitalization of at least $1 billion”).

[74]. PeopleSoft, for example, could not have exercised the rights under its poison pill unless it used a cashless exercise because the company did not have a sufficient number of shares of authorized common stock, even though PeopleSoft had almost twice as many authorized shares as issued shares.  See Subramanian, supra note 68, at 49 n.11.

[75]. For a review of the debate about the efficacy of the poison pill, see generally Lucian Arye Bebchuk, The Case Against Board Veto in Corporate Takeovers, 69 U. Chi. L. Rev. 973 (2002).

[76]. See id. at 988–90.

[77]. See id. at 991–94.

[78]. Id. at 991 (“[M]anagers might elect to block a beneficial acquisition in order to retain their independence.”).

[79]. Id. (“[M]anagers might use their power to extract not a higher premium for their shareholders but rather personal benefits for themselves.”).

[80]. For a review of the empirical studies, see id. at 992–93.

[81]. See Aaron Dixon, Delaware Chancery Court Provides Guidance for Terms of Top-Up Options (Mar. 7, 2011), http://www.alston.com
/mergersandacquisitionsblog/blog.aspx?entry=4255.

[82]. Davis Polk & Wardwell LLP, Top-Up Options – Looking Better and Better (Oct. 8, 2010), http://www.davispolk.com/files/Publication/eeadddb8-7d4a
‑4a94‑b4ad‑0ec5c2f1e32d/Presentation/PublicationAttachment/2f8068f4‑8c6b‑4723-8d2e-14008cae67ef/100810_topup_options.html.

[83]. See Dixon, supra note 81.

[84]. See supra note 82 and accompanying text.

[85]. See id.

[86]. See Dixon, supra note 81.

[87]. The minimum percentage of shares needed to be acquired at the tender offer to allow for the subsequent exercise of the top-up option is usually set at 50%.  See supra note 82 and accompanying text.

[88]. Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 253(a) (2010).

[89]. See Glassman v. Unocal Exploration Corp., 777 A.2d 242, 248 (Del. 2001) (“[A]ppraisal is the exclusive remedy available to a minority stockholder who objects to a short-form merger.”).

[90]. Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 253(a) (2010).

[91]. (Y+X) × (shares outstanding) / (100%+X) × (shares outstanding) = 90%

[92]. Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 153(a) (2010) (“[S]hares of stock with par value may be issued for . . . not less than the par value.”).

[93]. See, e.g., In re Appraisal of Metromedia Int’l Grp., Inc., 971 A.2d 893, 898–99 (Del. Ch. 2009) (“As part of the Top-Up Option, MergerSub paid MIG $2 million in cash and issued an unsecured promissory note to MIG in the amount of $358 million in exchange for the additional 200 million common shares. . . . MergerSub merged into MIG, with MIG as the surviving entity. . . . The promissory note given by MergerSub was cancelled because the obligor (MergerSub) and the obligee (MIG) on the promissory note became the same entity, making the note a nullity.”).

[94]. In Glassman v. Unocal Exploration Corp., the court held that a minority stockholder’s only recourse in challenging a short-form merger under 8 Del. Code § 253 was appraisal, stating that “we have held that claims for unfair dealing cannot be litigated in an appraisal. . . . stockholders may not receive recissionary relief in an appraisal.”  777 A.2d 242, 248 (Del. 2001) (reaffirming the interpretation of the appraisal statute’s scope set forth in Weinberger v. UOP, Inc., 457 A.2d 701 (Del. 1983)).

[95]. Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 267 (2010).

[96]. If the acquirer was able to receive at least 90% of the shares in the tender offer on her own, then there would have been no need for her to receive a top-up option.

[97]. Glassman, 777 A.2d at 248.

[98]. See, e.g., Bomarko, Inc. v. Int’l Telecharge, Inc., 794 A.2d 1161, 1177 (Del. Ch. 1999) (explaining that in addition to the appraisal remedy, other forms of equitable relief are available if the court finds that a long-form merger was not entirely fair).

[99]. See generally Ganor, Salvaged Directors or Perpetual Thrones?, supra note 10.

[100]. See 17 C.F.R. § 240.14d-10(a)(2) (2011) (“The consideration paid to any security holder for securities tendered in the tender offer is the highest consideration paid to any other security holder for securities tendered in the tender offer.”).

[101]. Cf. Mira Ganor, Manipulative Behavior in Auction IPOs, 6 DePaul Bus. & Com. L.J. 1 (2007) (demonstrating a strategic use of the downward sloping of the demand for shares).

[102]. In a typical top-up option agreement, the bidder undertakes to pay at the back-end squeeze-out the same price that he pays at the tender offer.  See, e.g., Olson v. ev3, Inc., No. 5583-VCL, 2011 Del. Ch. LEXIS 34, at *2 (Del. Ch. Feb. 21, 2011).  Without this undertaking the tender offer may be perceived as structurally coercive and could face judicial scrutiny.  Cf. In re Pure Res., Inc. S’holders Litig., 808 A.2d 421, 445 (Del. Ch. 2002).  The nontendering shareholders who oppose the subsequent short-form merger can, of course, use their appraisal right and receive the court-assigned fair market price of the shares.  The tendering shareholders will not have their price adjusted even if the tender price is lower.

[103]. See, e.g., Gholl v. eMachines, Inc., No. 19444-NC, 2004 Del. Ch. LEXIS 171, at *64–65 (Del. Ch. Nov. 24, 2004) (“Both TriGem and AOL . . . were past strategic partners of eMachines.  TriGem was being pressured by its biggest customer, and eMachines competitor, Hewlett Packard to distance itself from eMachines.  AOL had been a partner of eMachines under its old Internet-revenue business model, but was by late 2001, not a part of eMachines’ future plans.  These facts suggest that these stockholders may well have had a number of reasons for approving the Merger and thereby creating a liquidity event for themselves, other than a careful and reliable valuation analysis.”).

[104]. See Fried & Ganor, supra note 62, at 1003.

[105]. See, e.g., id. at 1004–05 (“Unfortunately, the appraisal remedy is an extremely weak constraint . . . [and c]ommentators have long recognized that appraisal is a remedy that few shareholders will seek under any circumstance.”).

[106]. See Peter V. Letsou, The Role of Appraisal in Corporate Law, 39 B.C. L. Rev. 1121, 1145 (1998).

[107]. See id. at 1156–60 (describing and analyzing procedural rules of appraisal remedy); Fried & Ganor, supra note 62, at 1003–05.

[108]. See, e.g., Fried & Ganor, supra note 62, at 1003–05; Richard T. Hossfeld, Short-Form Mergers After Glassman v. Unocal Exploration Corp.: Time to Reform Appraisal, 53 Duke L.J. 1337, 1353 (2004) (noting that shareholders seeking appraisal “must also hold an illiquid claim for almost two years, forgoing investment in other promising opportunities that may arise in the interim”); Alexander Khutorsky, Coming in From the Cold: Reforming Shareholders’ Appraisal Rights in Freeze-Out Transactions, 1997 Colum. Bus. L. Rev. 133, 160 (recommending setting “statutory rate of interest at the ‘borrower’s’ cost of debt” to fairly compensate dissenting shareholders, where “borrower” is majority shareholder); Robert B. Thompson, Exit, Liquidity, and Majority Rule: Appraisal’s Role in Corporate Law, 84 Geo. L.J. 1, 40 (1995) (describing the complicated requirements of appraisal and the unavailability of a class action suit).

[109]. See Gholl v. eMachines, Inc., No. 19444-NC, 2004 Del. Ch. LEXIS 171, at *72 (Del. Ch. Nov. 24, 2004).

[110]. Id. at *4.

[111]. Id. at *5.

[112]. Id.

[113]. Id. at *7.

[114]. Id. at *9.

[115]. Id.

[116]. Id. at *10.

[117]. Id.

[118]. Id. *10–11.

[119]. The bidding director’s offer represented a company value of $161 million, and the company had $165.2 million in cash.  See id. at *11, *69.

[120]. Id. at *11.

[121]. Id.

[122]. Id. at *14.

[123]. Id.

[124]. Id.

[125]. Id. at *60–61.

[126]. Id. at *63.

[127]. Id.

[128]. Id. at *69.

[129]. Id. at *73.

[130]. (339,000 + 1,005,600) = 1,344,600 shares, representing less than one percent of the total of 154,612,560 outstanding shares.  See id. at *2, *69.

[131]. 1,344,600 × $0.58 = $779,868.

[132]. See supra note 119 and accompanying text.

[133]. See eMachines, 2004 Del. Ch. LEXIS 171, at *14.

[134]. See Hossfeld, supra note 108, at 1337.

[135]. See eMachines, 2004 Del. Ch. LEXIS 171, at *14.

[136]. See Amended Class Action Complaint at ¶ 46, Mesa v. ZymoGenetics, Inc., No. 2:10-cv-01486 (W. D. Wash. Sept. 17, 2010), available at http://sec.gov
/Archives/edgar/data/14272/000119312510219518/dex99a11.htm.

[137]. See id.

[138]. See ZymoGenetics, Inc., Recommendation Statement (Schedule 14D-9), at Item 8 (Sept. 15, 2010), available at http://sec.gov/Archives/edgar/data
/1129425/000119312510210085/dsc14d9.htm (company’s description of the class actions).

[139]. See Amended Class Action Complaint, supra note 136, at ¶ 44.

[140]. See Recommendation Statement, supra note 138, at 38.

[141]. See Amended Class Action Complaint, supra note 136, at ¶ 37.

[142]. See Notice of Settlement of Class Action at 2, In re ZymoGenetics, Inc. S’holder Litig., No. 10-2-32389-9 (Wash. Super. Dec. 10, 2010), available at http://www.gilardi.com/pdf/zymgntcsnot.pdf.

[143]. Id.

[144]. Id.

[145]. In re Cogent, Inc. S’holder Litig., 7 A.3d 487, 492 (Del. Ch. 2010).

[146]. Id.

[147]. Id. at 494 (“3M did make its offer contingent on entering into retention arrangements with key employees”) (internal quotation marks omitted).

[148]. Id. at 495 (noting “Company D’s status as Cogent’s competitor”).

[149]. Id. at 498.

[150]. Id. at 506 n.60.

[151]. Id. at 498.

[152]. See, e.g., Alexia Tsotsis, Microsoft: “Yeah, We Tried to Acquire Facebook.”, TechCrunch (Dec. 9, 2010), http://techcrunch.com/2010/12/09/fritz
-lanman-microsoft-tried-to-acquire-facebook/ (quoting Mr. Zuckerberg telling Microsoft’s CEO: “I don’t want to sell the company unless I can keep control”).

[153]. Additionally, in this case the manager is a billionaire and thus may have a diminished marginal utility of money.

[154]. In re Cogent, Inc. S’holder Litig., 7 A.3d 487, 513 (Del. Ch. 2010).

[155]. Id.

[156]. See Top-Up Options – Looking Better and Better, supra note 82.

[157]. Other attempts to enjoin a two-step acquisition with a top-up option on the grounds of breach of fiduciary duties, arguing that the top-up options interfere with shareholder voting rights and enable managment to avoid a judicial review of fiduciary duties in favor of mere appraisal procedures, were not viewed favorably by the court.  See, e.g., Olson v. ev3, Inc., No. 5583-VCL, 2011 Del. Ch. LEXIS 34, at *6–8 (Del. Ch. Feb. 21, 2011) (reviewing a couple of earlier cases that either rejected the breach of fiduciary duty argument in the context of a top-up option or “described the plaintiffs’ claims as far from compelling”) (internal quotation marks omitted).

[158]. See Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 251(c) (2010) (requiring the approval of the holders of the majority of the shares for a long form merger).

[159]. See, e.g., Guhan Subramanian, Post-Siliconix Freeze-Outs: Theory and Evidence, 36 J. Legal Stud. 1, 3 (2007) (“Freeze-outs are generally subject to entire-fairness review by the Delaware courts, a stringent standard of review because of their self-dealing nature. . . . Even procedural protections such as the use of [a special committee] or [a majority of the minority] condition serve only to shift the burden of proof of entire fairness to the plaintiff.”).

[160]. Cf. id. at 4 (“Taken together, Siliconix and Glassman allow a controlling shareholder to avoid entire-fairness review by executing its freeze-out as a tender offer followed by a short-form merger.”).

[161]. See supra notes 101–05 and accompanying text.

[162]. See, e.g., Mallea, supra note 11 (“Tender offers give acquirers several advantages over traditional one step transactions, particularly the speed at which the transaction can be completed and the option to use a short-form merger once more than 90% of the shares have been tendered in the offer.”).

[163]. For the benefit of having more than one suitor, see, e.g., Karen Gullo & Adam Satariano, Citigroup Accused by Terra Firma of Fraud Over Sale of EMI, Bloomberg, (Dec. 12, 2009), http://www.bloomberg.com/apps/news?pid
=newsarchive&sid=aVHdh52RtPOQ&pos=6 (describing the suit brought by Terra Firma Capital Partners Ltd. against Citigroup for allegedly misrepresenting that another bidder was interested in acquiring EMI Group Ltd.).  In its complaint, Terra Firma argued it paid an inflated price for EMI because of Citigroup’s alleged misrepresentation.  Id.

[164]. See, e.g., Mallea, supra note 11.

[165]. See Stephen R. Volk et al., Developments in the Law of Mergers and Acquisitions: Developments in Defense, in 577 Corp. L. & Practice Course Handbook Series 287, 324–25 (1987).

[166]. The white squire should be distinguished from a white knight.  While both the white squire and the white knight support the target’s management and help the management defend against a hostile bidder, the white knight is a friendly acquirer who directly competes with the hostile bidder for the whole target.  See Black’s Law Dictionary 1734 (9th ed. 2009) (“A person or corporation that rescues the target of an unfriendly corporate takeover, esp. by acquiring a controlling interest in the target corporation or by making a competing tender offer.”).  The white squire, on the other hand, buys only a stake in the target but does not offer to buy the whole company.

[167]. Incumbents who want to entrench themselves by issuing new shares will do it selectively and find an investor who is going to serve as a white squire and support them.  The incumbents may not be able to rely on old white squires to continue to support them also in the future as the old investors may support the dissidents.  This is one reason why the managers may want to make sure they can continue and issue new shares also in the future.  To be sure, using a poison pill as an entrenchment mechanism does not bear this problem, since the managers apply their power to issue stock only as a deterrent, without actually issuing any shares or relying on new investors.

[168]. See Robert T. Grieves, B. Russell Leavitt & Adam Zagorin, Greenmailing Mickey Mouse, Time (June 25, 1984), http://www.time.com/time
/magazine/article/0,9171,926617,00.html.

[169]. See id.

[170]. See id. (“The strategy was to buy up other companies in order to diminish Steinberg’s share of Disney. . . . Steinberg sued to stop the deal, but a U.S. district court in Los Angeles ruled in favor of Disney.”).

[171]. See, e.g., Al Delugach, Walker Says He Was Unaware of Disney Strategy, L.A. Times (July 06, 1989), http://articles.latimes.com/print/1989-07-06
/business/fi-4208_1_disney-family (“[Disney] was putting 20% of its stock in the hands of Arvida’s controlling shareholders, the billionaire Bass family of Texas . . . .  [The “supermajority” provision of Disney’s bylaws] stated that a takeover not favored by the board must be approved by holders of 80% of the company’s stock.”).

[172]. Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 218 (2010).

[173]. See Schreiber v. Carney, 447 A.2d 17, 25–26 (Del. Ch. 1982).

[174]. Id. at 26; see also Hewlett v. Hewlett-Packard Co., No. 19513-NC, 2002 Del. Ch. LEXIS 44, at *11–12 (Del. Ch. Apr. 8, 2002) (“Management . . . may not use corporate assets to buy votes in a hotly contested proxy contest about an extraordinary transaction that would significantly transform the corporation, unless it can be demonstrated . . . that management’s vote-buying activity does not have a deleterious effect on the corporate franchise.”).

[175]. Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 242(a) (2010).

[176]. For the formula used to calculate the Delaware annual franchise tax, see How to Calculate Franchise Taxes, State of Del., http://corp.delaware.gov
/frtaxcalc.shtml (last visited Sept. 15, 2011).

[177]. Id.

[178]. See Aktiengesetz [AktG] German Stock Corporation Act, Sept. 6, 1965, BGBl I at § 202(1).

[179]. See id.

[180]. See supra note 24 and accompanying text.

[181]. NASDAQ OMX Group, Inc., Equity Rule 5635,

http://nasdaq.cchwallstreet.com/NASDAQTools/PlatformViewer.asp?selectednode=chp%5F1%5F1%5F4%5F2%5F8&manual=%2Fnasdaq%2Fmain%2Fnasdaq%2Dequityrules%2F (last visited Sept. 15, 2011).

[182]. Id. (“Nasdaq believes that in such situations the cap is defective because the presence of the alternative outcome has a coercive effect on the shareholder vote, and . . . will not accept a cap that defers the need for shareholder approval in such situations.”).

[183]. See, e.g., Section 1.4(a) of the Agreement and Plan of Merger and Reorganization between Rovi Corporation and Sonic Solutions at 13 (Dec. 22, 2010), available at  http://sec.gov/Archives/edgar/data/1424454
/000119312510287804/dex21.htm (“The obligation of the Company to issue and deliver shares pursuant to the Top-Up Option is subject only to the condition that no legal restraint (other than any listing requirement of any securities exchange) that has the effect of preventing the exercise of the Top-Up Option or the issuance and delivery of the Top-Up Option Shares in respect of such exercise shall be in effect.”).

[184]. Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 151(e) (2010).

[185]. Id.

[186]. See, e.g., the Model Stock Purchase Agreement of the National Venture Capital Association §2.5, http://nvca.org/index.php?option=com_content&view
=article&id=108&Itemid=136 (last visited Sept. 15, 2011) (providing that “[t]he Common Stock issuable upon conversion of the Shares has been duly reserved for issuance.”)

[187]. See Letter from Brian E. Covotta, O’Melveny & Myers LLP, in response to comment letter for Securities and Exchange Commission, available at http://sec.gov/Archives/edgar/data/1116755/000119312509220615/filename1
.htm (last visited Sept. 15, 2011).

[188]. See id.

[189]. See id. (“Because the Company did not have sufficient authorized shares of common stock, the Investor purchased . . . the Company’s remaining authorized shares . . . and 1,000,000 shares of a new series of Series A Convertible Preferred Stock . . . convertible into a number of shares of the Company’s common stock such that . . . [it] will, in the aggregate, represent 91.33% of the Company’s outstanding common stock.”).

[190]. Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 253 (2010).

[191]. Id.

[192]. See supra notes 85–90 and accompanying text.

[193]. It should be noted that unlike Delaware, California, as well as a few other jurisdictions that follow the Model Business Corporation Act, requires a class vote to approve a regular statutory long form merger.  See, e.g., Cal. Corp. Code § 1201(a) (2009).

[194]. If the charter includes a blank check preferred stock provision, the board of directors has full discretion to determine the rights assigned to these shares in accordance with section 102(a)(4) of the Delaware General Corporation Law.  See Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 102(a)(4) (2010).

[195]. The customary language in poison pills agreements provides that: “In the event that the Company does not have sufficient Common Shares available for all Rights to be exercised, . . . the Company may instead substitute cash, assets or other securities for the Common Shares for which the Rights would have been exercisable under this provision.”  Corvel Corp. Registration (Form 8-A12G/A) (Nov. 24, 2008), http://sec.gov/Archives/edgar/data/874866
/000089256908001502/a50604e8va12gza.htm; see also Sun Microsystems Inc. Registration (Form 8-A12G/A) (Sept. 26, 2002), http://sec.gov/Archives/edgar
/data/709519/000089161802004446/f83627a0e8va12gza.htm.

[196]. As in the case of a short-form merger, see supra note 97 and accompanying text.

[197]. Moran v. Household Int’l, Inc., 500 A.2d 1346, 1351 (Del. 1985) (“Appellants are unable to demonstrate that the legislature, in its adoption of § 157, meant to limit the applicability of § 157 to only the issuance of Rights for the purposes of corporate financing.  Without such affirmative evidence, we decline to impose such a limitation upon the section that the legislature has not.”).

[198]. See id.

[199]. See, e.g., Unocal Corp. v. Mesa Petroleum Co., 492 A.2d 946 (1985).

[200]. See Air Prods. & Chems., Inc. v. Airgas, Inc., Nos. 5249-CC & 5256-CC, 2011 Del. Ch. LEXIS 22, at *12 (Del. Ch. Feb. 15, 2011) (“[The poison pill] has given Airgas more time than any litigated poison pill in Delaware history . . . .”) (emphasis in original).

[201]. See, e.g., Gina Chon, “Poison Pill” Lives as Airgas Wins Case, MarketWatch (Feb. 16, 2011), http://www.marketwatch.com/story/story/print
?guid=42cccb5a-395a-11e0-a9aa-012128040cf6 (“Minutes after the judge’s ruling, Air Products dropped its effort to buy Airgas.”).

[202]. See Andrew L. Nichols, Shareholder Preemptive Rights, 39 Bos. Bar J. 4, 4 (1995).

[203]. See, e.g., John C. Coffee Jr., The Mandatory/Enabling Balance in Corporate Law: An Essay on The Judicial Role, 89 Colum. L. Rev. 1618, 1641 (1989) (“Preemptive rights . . . [was] a rule that was once mandatory, but evolved into a default rule.”).

[204]. See Aktiengesetz [AktG] German Stock Corporation Act, Sept. 6, 1965, BGBl I at § 202; Dr. Hurbert Besner et al., How to Implement a Standard US Venture Capital Term Sheet in Germany (Jan. 21, 2002), http://www.altassets.com/private-equity-knowledge-bank/country-focus/europe
/western-europe/germany/article/nz2955.html.

[205]. See, e.g., the Model Investors’ Rights Agreement of the National Venture Capital Association at 25 n.42, http://nvca.org/index.php?option=com
_content&view=article&id=108&Itemid=136 (last visited Sept. 15, 2011) (explaining that this is “commonly referred to as a[n] . . . ‘over allotment’ . . . provision and allows investors to purchase shares not purchased by other investors entitled to purchase rights”).

[206]. See supra notes 34–40 and accompanying text.

[207]. See supra note 24 and accompanying text.

[208]. See supra notes 178–79 and accompanying text.

[209]. I study only nonfinancial companies because financial companies, including real estate investment trusts (“REITs”), are subject to additional regulatory governance requirements that may have a substantial effect on the choice of the size of the excess ratio.  See, e.g., Lucian Arye Bebchuk & Alma Cohen, The Costs of Entrenched Boards, 78 J. Fin. Econ. 409, 418 (2005) (excluding REITs from the sample because such corporations “have their own special governance structure and entrenching devices”); Robert Daines, Does Delaware Law Improve Firm Value?, 62 J. Fin. Econ. 525, 530 (2001) (omitting financial firms from the tested sample because the special federal regulations may influence the corporate governance of such firms).

[210]. To be sure, this assumes that the managers ignore stock exchange restrictions on issuance of shares without shareholder approval, as they often do where top-up options are granted.  See supra note 183 and accompanying text.

[211]. See supra note 164 and accompanying text.

[212]. See, e.g., D. Gordon Smith, The Exit Structure of Venture Capital, 53 UCLA L. Rev. 315, 319–20 (2005).

[213]. See, e.g., id. at 345 (explaining that “[e]xit is not merely optional for venture capitalists. Most venture capital funds have a fixed life, usually ten years with an option to extend for a period up to three years”).

[214]. The size of the assets of the company may influence the choice of the size of the excess ratio at the public offering, because the size of the company may be connected to the likelihood of a future takeover.  An acquirer needs less financing to purchase a small firm, thus there are more potential acquirers that can acquire small firms, suggesting that smaller firms may have a higher incidence of being acquired.  In addition, a bigger company may be subject to more monitoring at the time of the initial public offering as well as later on.  The heightened scrutiny may limit the ability of management to go public with a high ratio and also limit the use of the power to issue stock in the future, even if there are sufficient authorized but unissued shares.

Article in PDF Form